Theological Phenomenology
Paul Tillich
We know of the Theological Circle, the Logical Tautology Circle, and now the Phenomenological Circle. All deductive non-contradictory axiomatic ideological systems are tautological. The essentialist/non-essentialist debate concerning the ultimate foundation of logical necessary is a debate about of the limits of the categories of finitude. Wittgenstein’s famous advice here is, “7. Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent.” This famous aphorism is Wittgenstein's summary of Kantian epistemology in total.
The Kantian block has always stood as the
limit of Reason long before phenomenology, or Wittgenstein appeared in history.
For Kant, the understanding supplies categorical forms (Space and Time) that
structure our experience of the sensible world, the thing-as-it-appears,
to which human knowledge is limited, while the intelligible thing-in-itself (or noumenal)
world is strictly unknowable (epistemologically blocked) to us. Remember
Heidegger’s other word for appearance, “Erscheinung,” which means
the way in which the thing appears, but is also a mark,
or sign of what a thing is. These problems of logical
circularity are a mark, or symptom of our finitude running up against the
infinite.
Theological Phenomenology:
- “The denial of reason in the classical
sense is antihuman because it is antidivine.” --Paul Tillich*
- · “...every
epistemology contains an implicit ontology.”- Paul Tillich
- ·“Every creative philosopher is a hidden theologian (sometimes even
a declared theologian).” – Paul Tillich
- “A system is a totality made up of
consistent, but not of deduced, assertions.” – Paul Tillich
*(Quotes found in Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology Vol.
I, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1951, 1957 & 1963.).
Theologian Paul
Tillich idealistically explains that, “Phenomenology is
a way of pointing to phenomena as they “give themselves,” without the
interference of negative or positive prejudices and explanations.” (Paul
Tillich, Systematic Theology Vol. I, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1951, 1957 & 1963, p. 106. Here after referred to as “ST1.” ).
However, unlike the positivistic empiricist that creates
distance between the object and himself, the theological phenomenologist must
have religious intuition that close the distance between himself and the object
in focus—this is because the “object” really is not an object at all, but other conscious human beings:
“A theological history of culture, which is the
attempt to analyze the theology behind all cultural expressions, to discover the
ultimate concern in the ground of a philosophy, a political system, an artistic
style, a set of ethical or social principles. This task is analytic rather than
synthetic, historical rather than systematic...It is an art as much as a
science to “read styles,” and it requires religious intuition, on the basis of
an ultimate concern, to look into the depth of a style, to penetrate to the
level where an ultimate concern exercises its driving power” (ST1, p. 39-20).
Tillich perceptively noted that, “Cognitive
distance is the presupposition of cognitive union.” (ST1, p. 94.). Yet,
he also warned, “The detachment required in honest theological work can
destroy the necessary involvement of faith. (ST1, p. 26.). Tillich
sees other problems with the phenomenological method. How is it to deal with
conflicting interpretations of phenomena? How is the criterion for ‘choosing
criterion’ even possible without being circular?
[My bold text for emphasis]
"However, the phenomenological method leaves one question
unanswered, which is decisive for its validity. Where, and to whom, is an idea
revealed? The phenomenologist answers: Take as an example a typical revelatory
event and see within it and through it the universal meaning of revelation.
This answer proves insufficient as soon as different and perhaps contradictory
examples of revelation are encountered by phenomenological intuition. What
criterion is to govern the choice of an example? Phenomenology cannot
answer this question. This points to the fact that while phenomenology is
competent in the realm of logical meanings, which was the object of the
original inquiries made by Husserl, the inventor of the phenomenological
method, it is only partially competent in the realm of spiritual realities like
religion” (ST1, p. 106-107).
The only way for Tillich to answer this question about the choice of a phenomenological example is, “...only if a critical element is introduced into “pure” phenomenology...This is 'critical phenomenology,' uniting an intuitive-descriptive element with an existential-critical element"(ST1, p.107). The biblical theologian’s exegesis is primarily “pneumatic” (Spiritual) or, what we would today call, “existential.”(ST1, p.35.).
There is also the problem of epistemological certainty. Certainty is easier in the technical sciences, but theological phenomenology is interested in the existential, or spiritual realm. In this realm our knowledge is incomplete,“...the infinite horizons of thinking cannot supply the basis for any concrete decision with certainty. Except in the technical realm where an existential decision is not involved, one must make decisions on the basis of limited or distorted or incomplete insights” ST1, p.35). Tillich believes all empirical theology will fail because 1.) The object of theology (our ultimate concern as human beings) is not an object of empirical-positivistic science. 2. Empirical theology cannot be tested by scientific standards of verification, but only by embracing a lifetime of participation in a concrete religious reality.
Tillich is speaking of a different kind of knowledge other
than technical knowledge, means-ends knowledge, or controlling knowledge. He is
instead speaking of, “knowledge [which] is more than a fulfilling: it also
transforms and heals: this would be impossible if the knowing subject were only
a mirror of the object, remaining in unconquered distance from it” (ST1,
p. 95). The problem with controlling knowledge is that it,“
‘objectifies’ not only logically (which is unavoidable) but also ontologically
and ethically.” (ST1, p. 97.).
Since the 1800s there have been extremist efforts to reduce all
of philosophy to scientific logic. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s first philosophical
work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1921) (free pdf)was
written on the assumption that natural language contained within it a hidden
calculus. Romanticism, philosophies of life, and existentialism were
antithetical schools of thought that attempted to resist this militant movement
for total domination by technical reason, or controlling knowledge.
Modern science and philosophy use “true” and “false” as
“qualities of judgments” and if judgments fail or are successful in describing
reality they are assigned values of truth or falsity. “But reality in itself
is what it is, and it can neither be true nor false”(ST1, p.
101).
That reality can be neither true, nor false (this is a function of reason and language), is exactly what Philosopher-Logician, Ludwig Wittgenstein said of the world and ethical values. Wittgenstein was the very first Logical Positivist in whose name the Vienna School of Logical Positivism was founded by the leading scientists of his era.
“6.41 The sense of the world must lie outside the
world. In the world everything is as it is and happens as it does happen. In it
there is no value—and if there were, it would be of no value.” -Wittgenstein,
Tractatus
“6.37 A necessity for one thing to happen because another
has happened does not exist. There is only logical necessity.” - Wittgenstein,
Tractatus
Tillich often uses the term “paradoxical” which means “against the opinion,” (During 1530–40 A.D., formed from the Greek word, paradoxon, from paradoxos, meaning conflicting with expectation; para-, beyond; see para + doxa, opinion) namely, the opinion of finite reason according to Tillich. However, there is refuge from the tyrannical rule of instrumental reason:
”Those elements of reality which cannot be reached
by controlling knowledge, like qualities, Gestalten, meanings,
ideas, values, and called “mysterious.” But the fact that they involve a
different cognitive approach does not make them mysterious. The quality of
color, or the meaning of an idea, or the nature of a living being is a mystery
only if the method of quantitative analysis is the pattern of all knowledge” (ST1,
p. 109).
The Methodology of Theological
Phenomenology:
- “Life processes have the character of
totality, spontaneity, and individuality. Experiments presuppose
isolation, regularity, and generality.”(ST1, p. 103.).
- “Reason as the structure of mind and
reality is actual in the processes of being, existence, and life. Being is
finite, existence is self-contradictory, and life is ambiguous.” (ST1, p.
103.).
The problem of instrumental reason is even more profound
in justifying methodology. In the modern age epistemology has divided itself
into two types of knowledge: controlling knowledge that is sure,
but insignificant and receiving knowledge that is significant
but not certain. Receiving knowledge is, “...’non-systematic’[which]
does not mean inconsistent; it only means non-deductive. And life is
non-deductive in all its creativity and eventfulness.” (Paul
Tillich, Systematic Theology Vol. II, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1951, 1957 & 1963, p. 5. Here after referred to as “ST2.”).
Ideologically, Reason has been reduced to the capacity for
“reasoning,” especially, to calculation. Contradictorily, even means-ends
“reasoning” has presuppositions of the nature of things that are not themselves
established by technical reason. Tillich ironically noted that, “Karl Marx
called every theory which is not based on the will to transform reality an
“ideology,” that is, an attempt to preserve existing evils by a theoretical
construction which justifies them”(ST1, p. 76).
This dethronement of Reason has an intellectual history
that can be traced back to Kant at least. After Hegel’s enormous philosophical
legacy and his all encompassing System faded into history, Reason become only
to be known as scientific calculation:
“In post-Kantian metaphysics reason forgot its bondage to
the categories of finitude. But this self-elevation to divine dignity brought
on dethronement and contempt of reason and made the victory of one of its
functions over all the others possible. The fall of a deified reason after
Hegel contributed decisively to the enthronement of technical reason in our
time and to the loss of the universality and the depth of ontological
reason” (ST1, p. 82).
“Ontological reason,” Tillich tells us, “can be defined as the structure
of the mind which enables it to grasp and to shape reality” (ST1,
p. 75).
“Methodology” is an ancient Greek word: méthodos systematic
course, equivalent to met- meta- + hodós way, road:
“A method is a tool, literally a way around, which must be
adequate to its subject matter...Therefore, no method can claim to be adequate
for every subject. Methodological imperialism is a dangerous as political
imperialism; like the later, it breaks down when the independent elements of reality
revolt against it”(ST1, p. 60).
With the dominance of logical positivism, operant conditioning behaviorist psychology, along
with developments in technology, even some philosophers will not acknowledge
anything that does not meet the standards of technical reason so questions of
existential concerns (Spirituality) are ruled out from contemplation a
priori. They are victims of the Materialist tautology: “Everything is
material; therefore, everything is material.”
The theological phenomenologist is emerged in the
Life-process and she brings her knowledge to the field of research in the form
of intuition just as other researchers in other disciplines do:
”The truth of their knowledge is verified partly by
experimental test, partly by a participation in the individual life with which
they deal. If this “knowledge by participation” is called “intuition,” the
cognitive approach to every individual life-process is intuitive. Intuition in
this sense is not irrational, and neither does it by-pass a full consciousness
of experimentally verified knowledge”(ST1, p.103).
How are we going to formulate any useful, or successful
criterion of any experimentation without begging the question of what is
useful, or successful? This is not an unusual dilemma faced by
hierarchical axiomatic epistemological systems and exact methodologies.
“Every concrete principle, every category and norm, which expresses more than pure rationality is subject to experimental or experiential verification. It is not self-evident, even if it contains a self-evident element (which, however, cannot be abstracted from it). Pragmatism is in no better position. It lacks a criterion. If the successful working of the principles is called the “criterion,” the question arises, “What is the criterion of success?” This question cannot be answered again in terms of success, that is, pragmatically. Neither can it be answered rationally except in a completely formalistic way”(ST1, p.104).
“Every concrete principle, every category and norm, which expresses more than pure rationality is subject to experimental or experiential verification. It is not self-evident, even if it contains a self-evident element (which, however, cannot be abstracted from it). Pragmatism is in no better position. It lacks a criterion. If the successful working of the principles is called the “criterion,” the question arises, “What is the criterion of success?” This question cannot be answered again in terms of success, that is, pragmatically. Neither can it be answered rationally except in a completely formalistic way”(ST1, p.104).
No comments:
Post a Comment