Thursday, March 21, 2019

Ideological Paradigms


Pure description is not possible. To observe is to create. There is no immaculate perception. Our first experience of the world is our very own ideas. One necessity for phenomenological description, according to Heidegger, is distinguishing between Schein (Appearing), meaning, semblance, “outward or surface appearance” and Erscheinung (Appearance) meaning the way in which the thing appears, but is also a mark, or sign of what a thing is. This is only one of at least three critical elements of phenomenological description -- the second being the question of how to select a phenomenological example for analysis. Tillich said, “...only if a critical element is introduced into “pure” phenomenology...This is “critical phenomenology,” uniting an intuitive-descriptive element with an existential-critical element. (ST1, p.107). Critical phenomenology is unavoidable.

“Lens” is a Metaphor, but “Paradigm” is an Explanation.

My favorite metaphor for a priori categories is the viewing lens. The lens metaphor explains everything: a limited, but filtered way of looking at phenomena. Another lens could bring to light other characteristics not seen in the previous lens. But the lens metaphor does not really explain anything. *The concept of “paradigm” not only has accidental benefits as a learning tool, but paradigms can actually explain how ideology influences our perception.

The Neo-Kantian understanding of absolute a priori categories, and relative a priori epistemological categories is important since paradigms function in the same way as a priori categories. How paradigms function like Neo-Kantian relative a priori categories will be shown point by point.

The absolute category is the original Kantian concept used to describe how consciousness shapes, or organizes sense data from perception to create experience. Consciousness use the transcendental ideals (meaning a priori) of space and time to comprehend the world as experience. In Kant’s “Critique of Pure Reason,” space and time are not named categories, but rather “pure a priori forms of intuition” meaning any object is known in advance of experience, and not because of experience. We cannot even think of an object not in time, or not in space because they are universal forms of sensibility which are the necessary conditions for the possibility of experience. But what the understanding cannot intuit a priori, it judges and synthesizes by logical types and constructs an structure of unifying logical concepts. Kant called these "Analytic of Concepts" which are made up of Judgments and Categories.

The Kantian school understands these categories as “absolute,” or the necessary conditions for the possible of experience. The Neo-Kantians hold that these necessary a priori concepts are functionally indistinguishable from a priori "relative" categories. Relative categories are unnecessary for experience, but they change the way perception is organized. Relative categories are not just formal static logical concepts, but are changing socio-historical-anthropological concepts by which cultures are organized by constructing a meaningful Lifeworld.

Conceptualizations can become "symbolized" to represent the relationship between concept and the particular in experience. Symbolization connects a perceptual sign with meaning. So uniting a sign and its meaning allows for distinctions in thought that are not found in fact: for example, thinking can distinguish the color and extension of an object, but the separation in not possible in fact.

The three elements necessary to critical phenomenological description is to 1.) identify relative a priori categories; 2.) distinguishing semblence and sign; and 3.) selecting a phenomenon for analysis.

Dr. Thomas Kuhn’s book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions(The University of Chicago Press, 1962, referred to as“SSR”), explores the evolution and revolutions of scientific paradigms and provides us with examples of how paradigms organize sense experience. Dr. Kuhn develops the term “paradigm” extensively in his work, and is worth a word study:

"The word paradigm has been used in science to describe distinct concepts. It comes from Greek "παράδειγμα" (paradeigma), "pattern, example, sample"- from the verb "παραδείκνυμι" (paradeiknumi), "exhibit, represent, expose," and that from "παρά" (para), "beside, by" + "δείκνυμι" (deiknumi), "to show, to point out". The original Greek term παραδείγματι (paradeigma) was used in Greek texts such as Plato's dialogue Timaeus (28A) as the model, or the pattern that the Demiurge (god) used to create the cosmos.(Wikipedia)."

The concept of paradigm is an important concept for demonstrating the principles that meaning is not external to consciousness, but is instead inter-subjective.  We examined Kant's transcendental analysis of consciousness, or the Subject. Kant’s meaning of “transcendental” is knowledge that is “a priori” to experience and is the necessary logical conditions for the possibility of experience.

The Functions of Paradigms

Dr. Thomas Kuhn does not provide a formal definition of paradigms; the concept is given definition by historical examples. He employs the concept of “paradigm” much like the term “hypothesis” is used in the physical sciences. A hypothesis postulates objective, or independently external entities that account for our experience of the world. Atoms, electrons, substance, and the classic laws of physics are hypotheses that give form and significance to phenomena. Kuhn names those commonly shared hypotheses “paradigms”(SSR, pp. 10-11).

" It has since become widely applied to many other realms of human experience as well even though Kuhn himself restricted the use of the term to the hard sciences. According to Kuhn, "A paradigm is what members of a scientific community, and they alone, share.” (The Essential Tension, 1997). Unlike a normal scientist, Kuhn held, “a student in the humanities has constantly before him a number of competing and incommensurable solutions to these problems, solutions that he must ultimately examine for himself.” (The Structure of Scientific Revolutions). A scientist, however, once a paradigm shift is complete, is not allowed the luxury, for example, of positing the possibility that miasma causes the flu or that ether carries light in the same way that a critic in the Humanities can choose to adopt a 19th century theory of poetics, for instance, or select Marxism as an explanation of economic behaviour. Thus, paradigms, in the sense that Kuhn used them, do not exist in Humanities or social sciences. Nonetheless, the term has been adopted since the 1960s and applied in non-scientific contexts. (Wikia) "

The scope of a paradigm can be a single proposition, theory, hypotheses, conceptual model, a picture, or axiomatic postulates—all these terms refer to relative ideological categories which organize and give significance to the otherwise chaotic world of sense impressions. Kuhn explored the characteristics of “paradigms” in his selected historical examples of scientific paradigmatic revolutions: “In its established usage, a paradigm is a accepted model, or pattern, and that aspect of its meaning has enabled me, lacking a better word, to appropriate ‘paradigm here”(SSR, p. 23).

Optics

One of Kuhn’s historical examples of how paradigms function in science and sometime conflict with one another can be found in the history of physical optics. There were primarily two theories, or “paradigms” which seems to account for the phenomenon of light. The way physical sciences are taught often leaves out the history of explanations of light.

”Today’s physics textbooks tell the student that light is photons, i.e., quantum-mechanical entities that exhibit some characteristics of waves and some of particles.  Re-search proceeds accordingly, of rather according to the more elaborate and mathematical characterization from which this usual verbalization is derived. That characteristic of light is, however, scarcely half a century old. Before it was developed by Planck, Einstein, and other early in this century, physics texts taught that light was transverse wave motion, a conception rooted in writings of Young and Fresnal in the early nineteenth century. Nor was the wave theory the first to be embraced by almost all practitioners of optical science. During the eighteenth century the paradigm of this field…taught that light was material corpuscles"(SSR, pp. 11-12). 

However, a closer look showed that light, or the photon did not act like a material corpuscle. In fact, light spreads out in all directions like a wave, but also light behaves like a particle moving in only one direction.

From the optics research example, two characteristics of a paradigm can be stated. 1.) Paradigms are models which attempt to explain a range of phenomena. As in the case of light, a sense impression is related to a frame of reference, i.e., light behaves as a wave, to give such sense impressions order and context. Paradigms explain things, or events in experience. 2.) Although paradigms can explain experience, other independently formulated paradigms can account coherently for the same range of experience. More than one paradigm can explain the same set of experiences, even when such paradigms may be incompatible with one another.

Electricity

Dr. Kuhn describes the variety of theories of electricity in the seventh and eighteenth century. One group thought of electricity as behaving like a fluid. Other scientists classified electricity according to primary a secondary properties such as attractive and repulsive effects of differently charged bodies.  Both schools of thought continued their research of electricity, but with differing paradigms, or models of how electricity behaved:

“If that body of belief is not implicit in the collection of facts—in which case more that “mere facts” are at hand—it must be externally supplied, perhaps by a current metaphysic, by another science, or by personal and historical accident. No wonder, then, that in the early stages of the development of any science different men confronting the same range of phenomena, but not, usually all the same particular phenomena, describe and interpret them in different ways”(SSR, pp. 16-17).

Each school of scientists approached the same range of phenomena with a, “body of intertwined theoretical and methodological” beliefs. And each group described and interpreted the same range of phenomena with differing results. One school of scientists held that electricity behaved as a fluid:

"Led by this belief, which could scarcely cope with the known multiplicity of attractive and repulsive effects, several of them conceived the idea of bottling the electrical fluid. The immediate fruit of their effort was the Leyden jar, a device which never have been discovered by a man exploring nature casually or at random"(SSR, page,17). 

The fluid paradigm interpreted the behavior of electricity to allow for developing the capacitor. The fluid paradigm determined what phenomena were relevant to research, and so research was more than merely collecting facts, but organizing facts into a certain pattern which fit the fluid paradigm. This organizing, or structuring is basically what paradigms do.

From these examples we can list additional characteristics of paradigms.

1.)  Paradigms are in principle not factual, but are interpretations of facts. A range of phenomena will appear differently according to the paradigm through which the world is viewed.

2.)  Paradigms set up, or organize phenomena according to a pattern unique to itself and supply a context to an otherwise chaotic mass of facts. Paradigms form patterns within experience.

3.)  Paradigms are attention directing by emphasizing a certain range, or domain of phenomena while other phenomena are viewed as less relevant, or irrelevant all together.
Oxygen

Next, Kuhn directs our attention to three scientists in the 1770s who isolated the gas oxygen, but were not able to give it proper significance within the scientific theories of chemistry in their era (SSR, p. 53-56). Swedish scientist C. W. Scheele was first to claim discovery of oxygen, but last to publish his findings.  J. Priestley isolated and studied the gas in 1774 -1775 only claim  to described it as “dephlogisticated air.” The theory of thermodynamics during Priestley’s time postulated a hypothetical substance (pholgiston: Ancient Greek φλογιστόν phlŏgistón for "burning up") thought to be present in all things and released as flames during the process of combustion. This theory accounted for the phenomenon of mass loss when something such as wood was consumed by fire. However, this explanation could not account for the increase in weight by certain metals after exposure to heat. Only later did this phenomenon have significance for the scientist and rejected the pholgistic theory.

Lavoisier, the third scientist, questioned the pholgistic theory in 1775.  Kuhn points out that Lavoisier’s rejection of this older theory of thermodynamics enabled Lavoisier to recognize its importance. Priestley never really understood the meaning of finding this gas, oxygen. Kuhn writes,

"What the work on oxygen did was give much additional form and structure to Lavoisier’s earlier sense that something was amiss. It told him a thing he was already prepared to discover—the nature of the substance that combustion removes from the atmosphere…. The fact that a major paradigm revision was needed to see what Lavoisier saw must be the principal reason why Priestley was, to the end of his long life, unable to see it"(SSR,p. 56).

We can summarize some important characteristics of paradigms in this example:

1.)  What is considered a “fact” is relative to the paradigm from which one operates. A “fact” is paradigmatically defined. Any phenomenon that does not fit coherently in a paradigm is simply overlooked, or not given relevant importance. Paradigms determine facticity. We have already discussed this extensively in other terminology.

2.)  Paradigms are applied a priori to facts by interpreting and structuring information.

3.)  And this is the most important characteristic of paradigms: paradigms are themselves non-factual. The “logical status” of paradigms seems to be non-factual. This non-factual aspect of paradigms makes them enigmatic when a scientist must choose between competing paradigms. The epistemological question of paradigm choice cannot be resolved by appealing to experience alone.

(My bold emphasis).
"Like the choice between competing political institutions, that between competing paradigms proves to be a choice between incompatible modes of community life. Because it has that character, the choice is not and cannot be determined merely by the evaluative procedures characteristic of normal science, of these depend in part upon a particular paradigm, and that paradigm is at issue. When paradigms enter, as they must, into a debate about paradigm choice, their role is necessarily circular. Each group uses its own paradigm to argue in that paradigm’s defense"(SSR, p. 94). 

Any debate about which paradigm should be incorporated into one’s thinking cannot be settled by appealing to facts alone since what is considered a “fact” depend upon the paradigm itself. Paradigms make available a range of  “perceptual possibilities” (SSR, p. 120). By the use of paradigms there is a “transformation in the range of vision” in which new objects appear and new phenomena are discovered. Kuhn wrote, “ What a man sees depends both upon what he looks at and also upon what his previous visual-conceptual experiences has taught him to see”(SSR, p. 113).
Summary of Paradigm Characteristics:

·Universal: Paradigms attempt to form a transcendental (a prior) universal whole to give meaning to the world of singular sensible impressions. Paradigms relate particulars to a universal frame of reference so that a particular sensible impression (using our five senses) is related to a universal frame of reference to give order, unity, structure, and context to experience.

·Non-Empirical: Since singular sensible impressions are understood through a conceptual principle, paradigms define the factual by providing a medium, or concept through which experiential datum can be interpreted as fact.  A paradigm relates facts to concepts to form a unified picture of the whole experience.

·Interpretative: Sensible information is not given without first being filtered through a medium, or concept. This information is organized or structured according to some point of reference. Sensory information is modified by exclusion of experience and inclusion of unconscious meanings. Henri Bergson wrote, 

“...concepts, laid side by side, never actually give us more that artificial reconstruction of the object, of which they can only symbolize certain general, in a way, impersonal aspects; it is therefore useless to believe that with them we can seize a reality of which they present to us the shadow alone” (Henri Bergson, An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans, T. E. Hulme, Indianapolis; Bobbs-Merrill,1978, p.29).

·Totalities: Ernst Cassirer speaks of this same process as the mind, “weaving the particulars into  a system.” Paradigms attempts to form this totality which we call the “world,” or better yet Husserl’s “Lifeworld.” Cassirer described this activity of consciousness as... 

“The aim of theoretical thinking as we have seen, is primarily to deliver the contents of sensory or intuitive experience from the isolation in which they originally occur. It causes these contents to transcend their narrow limits, combines them in a definite order, in an all-inclusive context. It proceeds ‘discursively,’ in that it treats the immediate content only as a point of departure, from which it can run the whole gamut of impressions in various directions, until these impressions are fitted together into one unified conception, one closed system. In this system, there are no more isolated points; all its members are reciprocally related, refer to one another; illumine and explain each other. Thus every separate event is ensnared, as it were by invisible threads of thought, that bind it to the whole. The theoretical significance which it receives lies in the fact that it is stamped with the character of this totality” (Ernst Cassirer, Language and Myth, trans, S.K. Langer, New York: Dover Pub., 1946, p. 32).

·Categorical: Paradigms reduces the world of objects and events to generalized notions of which any individual event, or object can belong. Categories are classes, or types, through which experience is organized and known. “Category” is understood here in a Kantian sense: categories are the fundamental a priori forms through which the phenomenal world is perceived. (The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1967 ed., “Categories,” by M. Thompson.).

·Ontological: Paradigms are concerned only with the particular object, or entity. Intellectual reflection is directed toward the factors which give the world of particular experience meaning, and context. Reflection in this case seeks to examine those categorical factors which make the empirical possible—to examine those, “invisible threats of thought” that unites the whole. Paradigms provides a foundation for empirical concreteness by going beyond the facts to the “factors which make facts recognizable" (One-Dimensional Man, Herbert Marcuse,1964, p. 106).

·Paradigms are Circular.


*Thinking with Epistemological Paradigms

A paradigm is a good organizational tool to learn philosophical systems (Hegel, Kant, Kierkegaard) faster, and make impromptu contrasts/comparisons on the fly between different philosophies. Paradigms distances you from philosophies much like the “epoche” was meant to. Thinking in terms of paradigms will also help with your writing style by providing a coherent narrative voice.

Most importantly, use paradigms as a heuristic device to understand the elements and relational dynamics of a selected topic. There is no need to proclaim eternal faith in paradigms--just use them as an intellectual tool. Also, the Hegelian dialectical method of viewing historical elements as thesis, antithesis, and synthesis is also a useful analytical tool that can be used purely heuristically to construct a powerful philosophical analysis.

Lastly, understanding and using paradigmatic thinking is also helpful for understanding Martin Heidegger’s theology and philosophy.

No comments:

Post a Comment