Saturday, December 25, 2021

Appendix G, Part III: Second Counter-Argument Realism and Antirealism

 

Second Counter-Argument: MacIntyre as an Aristotelian-Thomist Realist contradictorily embraces Anti-realist Epistemology.

“What I learned from Kuhn, or rather from Kuhn and Lakatos read together, was the need first to identify and then to break free from that framework and to inquire whether the various problems on which I had made so little progress….”--Alasdair MacIntyre (pdf.) 

“Kuhn, however, is Kant on wheels.”
--Peter Lipton (pdf.)

 

Deconstructing the Devil, Kant, and Thomas Kuhn 

The devil here is referring to postmodernism. What could “Kant on wheels” possibly mean? We must first consider certain aspects of Kant’s philosophy of knowledge in order to understand MacIntyre’s embrace of anti-realist epistemology in the form of Thomas Kuhn’s famous study of the nature of scientific revolutions, and the role paradigms have in scientific research. Consistent with other postmodernist critics today, After-Virtue is virulently anti-Kantian in regard to both ethics and epistemology. MacIntyre’s epistemology is inadequate for addressing these difficult questions of ethics and scientific epistemology forcing him to resort to an unconscious yet skillful slight-of-hand by introducing Kantian idealism in the disguise of Thomas Kuhn. This ideological swap is done repeatedly with other philosophical concepts by replacing historical teleologyethical intuition, and ought/is dichotomy with his anti-postmodern left hand and giving back with his conservative right hand intentionally impaired concepts such as “tradition,” “telos,” and “narrative” stripped of their dynamic mind-dependent functions and meanings. 

This second specific counter-argument points to an inadequacy of his version of Aristotelian realism; to compensate, he is forced to present a lobotomized version of Kantian critical idealism wearing the mask of Kuhnian paradigmatic epistemology. Yet, Kuhn is not mentioned in any of his four books After-Virtue (1981)Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (1988 ); Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry (1990); Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues (1999) of which the last three books are elaborations of the themes in After Virtue. He instead expresses Kuhnian hypotheses through the pseudonym of “Hamlet” in his essay, “Epistemological Crisis” (pdf.). An ”Emma” works within a paradigm model, and a Hamlet challenges the model with a new paradigm. 

I have written in detail on Thomas Kuhn’s famous theory of scientific paradigms (Ideological Paradigms) and Kantian critical theory. Kuhnian epistemology is an anti-realist epistemology (The Genealogy of Kuhnian Antirealism video lecture by Paul Hoyningen). What is the difference between realist and anti-realist epistemology? Why does MacIntyre need postmodern Kuhnian epistemology to critique postmodernism, and to understand the meaning of virtue? 

Paradigms of Epistemological Realism and Anti-realism 

Epistemological realism and anti-realism can be reduced to six key components. Dr. Lee Braver, professor of philosophy at Hiram College, Ohio, has written an excellent book with the beautiful title of “A Thing Of This World: A history of Continental Anti-Realism,” (2007), Northwestern University Press, Evanston, Illinois. Braver created two powerful realist (positivist) and anti-realist (Kantian) matrices to organized, compare, and help memorize key principles of these models of knowledge (Braver, p. 15-30 passim). I will briefly summarize each principle, but will focus on three that are most relevant to this polemical study. Braver named these constituent theses of the definition of realism as the following: 

Realism1=Independence: What is real is independent from any idea, statement, or examination by the self. The world, objects, and situations are separate from the mind and do not depend on thought. This metaphysical principle of realist detachment is the first, and some say, complete definition of realism.  

R2=Correspondence: However, there is also the possible epistemological congruous correlation (knowledge) of subjective ideas, beliefs, and words (mind) with objective things, objects, and states of affairs (world). This view is called the correspondence theory of truth: a true proposition in this theory is one that corresponds to the state of something in the world, or a fact. A belief is said to be true if it corresponds to an existing object. Historically, there are differences among logicians and philosophers on whether truth is an attribute of an object, or a proposition, or belief (for greater detail see: Bertrand Russell's Critique of Fregean Logico-Mathematical Objects). 

R3=Uniqueness: There is only one truth, and one complete description of all reality. This principle is known as metaphysical realism claiming, “There exists at least ideally, a full knowledge of all of the Forms which would constitute the complete knowledge of all natural kinds about which there could be no legitimate disagreement.13 This view is also attributed to “Aristotelian realism…(Braver, p.18 ).” This is “knowledge by definition” as the single unique self-sorting self-identifying world of objects presents themselves appearing the same to all potential observers (Ibid.). Braver points out that Aristotelian realism is the combination of R1, R2, and R3. 

R4=Bivalence: This is the semantic view that all meaningful sentences are determined to be either true or false with no other third possibility, and is named the law of the excluded middle. Some charge that bivalence disregards process, or becoming within a dynamic world. Frege, Russell, and the early Wittgenstein combined bivalence with logical atomism, and set theory to construct symbolic truth-tables of variables (p and q) and constant logical operators (if, then, either, or, and) to determine consistency; that is to say, validity of deductive inferences. This is a radical shift from metaphysics to the philosophy of language where truth is not epistemic, nor dependent on verification, but rather “…that human access to evidence is wholly irrelevant to what the truth is (Ibid., p .21).”

“…the passivity of a thinking which only needs a mouth agape.”
—Hegel in“The Difference between Fichte and Schelling’s System of Philosophy.” 

R5=Passive knower: With this epistemic model the knower receives knowledge like the sun warms a stone. The subject is a passive receiver of knowledge from the independent external world; that the observer abstain from contributing any subjective influence to the self-contained object is essential for undistorted truth corresponding to reality. A personal creative interpretation of the world is not allowed in this version of non-participating epistemic objective realism. 

R6=Realism of the Self: This sixth thesis of realism is the contribution of Kant that states all observers at all times see the world through the same conceptual lenses universally. All subjects contribute to the object in the same way through the a priori forms of sense intuition (space and time) and the a priori categories of the understanding (Kant’s table of analytic concepts) for they are the necessary conditions for the possibility of sense experience and knowledge. I cannot imagine an object, or point not in space and time, and you cannot either. Everything we know about the world must first be filtered through the lenses of our perceptual nervous system. 

Realism and Anti-realism Paradigm Entailment

 

This transition point to anti-realism is a good place to bring up once again Dr. Kai Nielsen’s study of entailment relations discussed regarding metaethical and normative theses where we found that some relations are neutral and others non-neutral. Braver tells us that realist and anti-realist ideas can be “mixed and matched” without having to reject the other theses so it is not a matter of anti-realism being diametrically opposed point by point with realism: the relationships between the two paradigms are mostly neutral to use Nielsen’s definition (Ibid., p .38 ).” This means that the passive knower (R5) could be replaced with an active knower (A5) without necessary falsifying the other theses of realism. Braver’s matrices show just how revolutionary Kant’s critical theory is when compared with metaphysical realism that was the dominant epistemological paradigm of his time (Ibid., p. 35). Kantian antirealism requires by necessity the active contributing constructing creative self to achieve knowledge.

 

“Socrates says that when we posit flute-playing we must also posit a flute-player….”

-Kierkegaard

 

Anti-Realism1=Mind-Dependent: Noumena (things-in-themselves) are independent of mind (R1), but phenomena (appearances) are mind-dependent (A1) representations of the active knower (A5) (Ibid., p. 39). Plato also has a two-worlds view of appearances and the eternal ideal forms that objectively exist behind them. For Kant the noumenal is the unperceivable non-sensible limit of Reason, analogous to Wittgenstein’s standpoint that language is the limit of our world. An epistemology of limitation is not self-contradictory and is plausible.

 

A2=Rejection of Correspondence Theory of Truth: Kant’s correspondence theory of truth corresponds not to the inaccessible unknowable noumenal, but to the knowable accessible phenomenal (Ibid., p. 44). The sensible manifold of experience (intuition) is only given if organized according to the a priori concepts of space, time, quantity, quality, relation, and modality; otherwise, our perceptual lens would be blind. Correspondence now means congruence to the subjective a priori structural forms of sensibility which all perception must first be mediated before we experience the world of things, objects, and states of affairs.

 

A3=Ontological Pluralism: Kant embraces R3 by way of the necessary table of categories that are the lenses by which all phenomena is interpreted in the same way for all observers. Instead of a perspectiveless objectivity, Kant presents the necessary concepts for the possibility of experience as the next best standard of objectivity (Ibid., p. 56). Braver shows how Kant achieves a unique single reality (R3) by rejecting the passive knower (R5), and mind-independent world (R1) by substituting the active knower (A5) who provides the universal a priori principles of perception (R6). Hegel describes the necessary historical forms of life in Western thought (sense-certainty, observing reason, ethics, Enlightenment, understanding, religion) that go through an advancing teleological cycle of historical conflicts and resolutions, but he is not a relative idealist: rather, Hegel is an absolute idealist believing in only one reality because there is only one universal Reason, or Mind. On the other hand, Kant’s table of categories, and the transcendental cognito are logical presuppositions that are completely ahistorical.

 

A4=Rejection of Bivalence: Kant accepts bivalence in the phenomenal realm, but not the noumenal realm that include belief in a god, immortality, and human autonomy (Freedom). This ontological division of reality offers one world that can be known wherever the categories of perception are applied to phenomena, and the other unknowable region of things-in-themselves. Adorno coined the term “Kantian block” to describe this Kantian barrier that limits reason to phenomenal experience otherwise thought succumbs to the tradition of dogmatic metaphysics. Hegel’s standpoint rejects bivalence as blind to historical change and the process of becoming in history. For Kant and Wittgenstein bivalence only apply to the experiential phenomenal world of appearances, and not noumenal reality.

.

A5=Active Knower: Kant needs the active knower (A5) as the correspondent to phenomena (R2)—not unknowable noumenon (R1) to establish a fixed unique single reality (R3) universal to all observers (R6) (Ibid., p.44, 57).

 

Neo-Kantian Relative Categories on “Wheels”

 

Some readers would object to Kant’s thesis that phenomena is processed the same for all observers since persons clearly have different interpretations of the same phenomenon otherwise there would be no disagreement about what is real. We must remember again Kant’s transcendental idealism is referring to the necessary conditions for the possibility of experience and not what is unnecessary for experience. The Neo-Kantian distinction between absolute a priori category, and a relative epistemological category is important since paradigms function in the same manner as the lenses of absolute a priori categories. This distinction of absolute and relative apriority can be found in the works on culture of the last great philosopher of the Marburg School of Neo-Kantianism, Ernest Cassirer (1874-1945).  A relative a priori concept, for example, could be the Ptolemaic geocentric conception of the sun’s orbit around earth; however, the opposing Copernican heliocentric universe is an opposing model of earth’s orbit, but neither of these two astronomical orbital paradigms are necessary to experience the darkness of night, or the light of day—in fact, the movement of the sun across the sky appears the same to the ordinary observer embracing either paradigm.

 

The orthodox Kantian School understands the table of categories as “absolute,” or necessary for all experience—even for the angels! The Neo-Kantian thesis is that necessary a priori concepts are functionally indistinguishable from "relative" a priori concept. Relative categories are unnecessary for experience, and yet still contribute to constructing the object by the way perception is pre-organized and pre-structured. Relative categories are not just a formal static internal set of logical concepts, but are changing socio-historical-cultural lenses that organize and reorganize experience by creating a meaningful lifeworld that varies from peoples, geographies, and histories—these paradigms are “on wheels,” or variable. It is these unnecessary dynamic cultural paradigms of perception that partly account for the vast multiplicity of worldviews.  I noticed that Kant, Braver, nor Kuhn explicitly mention this distinction of absolute and relative apriority.

 

MacIntyre wrote: "Kant presented as the universal and necessary principles of the human mind turned out in fact to be principles specific to particular times, places and stages of human activity and enquiry…"Kant took to be the principles and presuppositions of natural science as such turned out after all to be the principles and presuppositions specific to Newtonian physics... Thus the claim to universality foundered. (AV., p. 266)."

 

This comment suggests that the Neo-Kantian relative/absolute distinction is not fully understood. MacIntyre rejects Kant’s transcendentalism, but embraces Kuhnian paradigms that function as relative categories and this exposes his realist epistemology to the pluralism of relativistic anti-realist Kuhnian paradigms.

 

…next:

Third Counter-Argument:

MacIntyre leaves the door open for Relativistic Historicism while advocating a particular tradition of ethical thought.

Appendix G, Part II: After-Virtue’s Critique of Metaethical Emotivism

 

After-Virtue’s Critique of Metaethical Emotivism 

 

After Virtue begins with a phalanx of arguments against the malaise of modernism and in particular against the poor British philosopher, G.E. Moore; and I say poor because the utilitarian was portrayed as a hedonistic aesthete that exposed Western Civilization to the ethics of “it’s all good” Emotivism. Moore rejects idealism whether British Hegelianism, Transcendental Kantianism, or German Continental philosophy. Emotivism is the metaethical theory that asserts statements of right and wrong are expressions of approval, or disapproval. I will use the terms statements, sentences, assertions, and propositions interchangeably unless otherwise noted for detailed analysis. Oxford philosophical logician, W.E. Johnson defined twenty distinct meanings of “proposition.”  Even some knowledgeable students of British analytic empiricism would find it difficult to climb this first obstacle while other readers are shepherded through the book as it progresses from the critique of Emotivism (AV, p. 14), then links to R.M. Hare (Ibid, p. 20, 26, 113), bumps into Sartre (Ibid, p. 26), then to the totalitarian social manipulation dealer, Max Weber (Ibid, p. 23-24). It’s your brain on Emotivism. Any systematic philosophy whatsoever can be corrupted and used to manipulate others, which is why we should always ask Moore’s open question, “…but is it good?

 

The reader would be in much better shape knowing in advance the distinctions between normative ethical propositions (what ought to be done), and metaethical propositions (what is); the various relations of entailment between metaethical theories and normative rules of right and wrong; familiarity with the Humean “no ought from is” (NOFI) problem; the difference between cognitivist and noncognitivist schools of thought; and the methodologies employed by Moore in his famous (or infamous) work, “Principia Ethica (1930).” I want to discuss these and other such topics to show that metaethical Emotivism is not based on some arbitrarily conclusion, but arrived at by force of rational analysis.

 

Scottish philosopher, David Hume, famously argued that no normative ought statement can be derived from an empirical statement; in other words, values cannot be derived from facts. Evaluative moral statements cannot be inferred from factual statements alone. A metaethical statement of the socio-psychological fact that “Humans are empathetic,” to the moral statement “One should be empathetic of others” cannot be logically based on empirical factual statements describing human behavior. Ought statements are modal assertions of possible worlds or situations, whereas factual (synthetic) statements are indicative describing some actual state of affairs. 

Entailment of Metaethical and Normative Theses 

Philosopher Dr. Kai Nielsen (University North Carolina) has studied the relationship between normative and metaethical theses and found that some metaethical statements are neutral to normative claims while some others are not neutral (Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Collier Macmillan (1972), Vol. 3, p. 120). 

Take propositions (q) and (p) for example: simple entailment means if (p) is true, then (q) is true, and if (q) is false, (p) is false. 

However, if (p) is presupposed by (q) the relation of entailment is different as in the example below: 

(q) The professor’s students are Irish

(p) The professor has students

 

If (p) is false (the professor has no students), then (q) (students are Irish) and not-q (students are not Irish) are void since there are no students.  

However, there is an example of (q) being false without (p) being false: 

(q) The professor’s students are Irish

(p) The professor has students 

If it is false that (q) the professor’s students are Irish, it does not follow that (p) the professor has no students. In this case (q) is false, but (p) can still be true (the students could be Canadian).  The statement (q) in this case is neutral in relation to (p). 

Now let’s look at the same pattern with metaethical theses statements:

 

Likewise, some metaethical propositions do not presuppose a normative rule. Let (q) represent a metaethical thesis, and (p) a normative rule.

 

(q) Ethical statements can be true or false (Cognitivist thesis)

(p) Vegetarianism is good (normative statement)

 

If (q) is false, then (p) is void. The normative statement (p) cannot be true if the metaethical thesis statement (q) is false. The relation in this case is not neutral.

 

However, in the case of Emotivism that asserts ethical statements only imply, or display an expressive-aesthetic attitude toward ethical norms, the entailment relation does not hold in the converse:

 

(q) Ethical statements are expressions of emotion (Emotivism)

(p) Vegetarianism is good

 

If (p) is false, then (q) is neutral: (q) does not presuppose any normative ethical rule. For Moore, the role of the philosopher is to determine the metaethical is, and not be a moral counselor of oughts. Metaethics is helpful in clarifying and understanding normative statements. This complex issue of entailment relationship will come up again when we examine the theses of realist and anti-realist paradigms.

 

The “Good” Captain

 

MacIntyre completely rejects the ought/is dichotomy and presents an argument from logician A.N. Prior to defend this position (AV. p. 148 ). However, After Virtue’s summary description of the ought/is division is excellent:

 

"Some later moral philosophers have gone so far as to describe the thesis that from a set of factual premises no moral conclusion validly follows as 'a truth of logic', understanding it as derivable from a more general principle which some medieval logicians formulated as the claim that in a valid argument nothing can appear in the conclusion which was not already in the premises (AV. p. 56-57)."

 

In other words--the NOFI thesis known as Hume’s Law--states values cannot be derived from facts. Within deductive logical one cannot validly infer a conclusion containing moral claims from non-moral premises. In opposition to Hume’s Law, MacIntyre wants to show A.N. Prior’s counter-example wherein a value statement can be derived from a factual premise containing no value statements:

 

1. 'He is a sea-captain' (Is)

2. Therefore: “He ought to do whatever a sea-captain ought to do.”

 

Unfortunately, A.N. Prior’s counter-argument is deeply flawed and has instead committed the "One word, one meaning fallacy (Copleston, vol. 8, pt. II, p. 178 )(pdf. of Copleston’s History of Philosophy, Vol..2, 3, 7, 8, 9).” If the term “captain” is referenced in a Thesaurus, a number of synonyms appear such as “commander,” “officer,” and “boss” that by definition mean the sea-captain has authority and a duty (δέον, deon as in ethical deontology). Prior’s syllogism already has embedded in the premise a copula linking “captain, to “duty.” Dr. Prior merely deduced a moral conclusion from a disguised moral premise—an overlooked tautology. One cannot derive normative conclusions (ought) from non-normative premises (descriptions). 

Moore believes any inquiry into a definition of goodness must distinguish between good conduct, and good things for if we only are searching for what property makes for good conduct, then we may mistake it for some property not shared with other good things; otherwise, any analysis falls into confusion (Ethica, para. 1, 6). MacIntyre does not seem to be impressed with Moore’s efforts writing, “Moore's arguments at times are “…obviously defective-he tries to show that 'good' is indefinable, for example, by relying on a bad dictionary definition of 'definition' –and a great deal is asserted rather than argued (AV. p. 16).” MacIntyre opposes Hume and Moore’s NOFI position in order to preserve his belief in naturalism that postulates ethical judgments and values are properties which can be derived from facts about the world. One can get a better understanding of these various metaethical paradigms if we group them into generalized schools of thought of which there are many significant, but subtle variations. 

Metaethical Paradigms 

“6.41 The sense of the world must lie outside the world. In the world everything is as it is and happens as it does happen. In it there is no value—and if there were, it would be of no value.”Tractatus (pdf.) 

Naturalism is a metaethical theory asserting that ethical propositions are either objectively true or false in referencing the world independent of thought while rejecting Hume’s Law that absolutely separates fact from values. However, ethical properties are definable and can be reduced to non-ethical properties as with hedonism which reduces goodness to pleasure.  According Dr. Richard B. Brandt, some forms of naturalism are very similar to emotive theory (Encycl. Vol. 2, p. 486). Since naturalism can reduce moral properties to non-moral attributes the study of ethics can be an empirical naturalistic science

For nonnaturalistsgood” is an indefinable, simple, and unanalyzable primitive term (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 100). Moore argues that good is a nonnatural indefinable property and can only be known directly such as a color can be experienced directly, but yet impossible to describe to a person that has never seen color. Nonnaturalism is a reaction to the aporias of naturalism. I believe that on this issue Wittgenstein concluded good is a nonnatural property by his famous quote in the Tractatus, “6.522 There is indeed the inexpressible. This shows itself; it is the mystical.” Bertrand Russell wrote: “The whole subject of ethics, for example, is placed by Mr. Wittgenstein in the mystical, inexpressible region (Tractatus, p. 18 ).” 

The nonnaturalist believes that naturalists are confusing good things with the analytic tautological meaning of good which Moore named “The Naturalistic Fallacy.” This fallacy originates from reading the “is” of attribution (adjectively) as an “is” of identity (substantively). For example, if pleasure “is” good, then good is identical to pleasure. If we equate the meaning of “good” with some determinate characteristic, we make it impossible to discuss whether that characteristic is good. If these things, objects, or attributes are what “good” means, then there is no point in asking whether they are good! Philosopher Nicolai Hartmann wrote,“ ‘beauty’ is to ‘value’ as ‘red’ is to ‘colored’ (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 101).” Moore’s nonnaturalism is still debated today. Surprisingly, it is other nonnaturalists like A.N. Prior that MacIntyre appealed to for his counter-argument against Emotivism. A.N. Prior believes that the naturalistic fallacy is merely a “definist fallacy” not particular to nonnaturalism so they are not logically excluded from arguing that moral terms can be defined in non-moral terms (Ibid., p. 101). But Socrates would still ask, “Why can you only describe to me the parts of virtue, and not what virtue is as a whole?” And Moore would ask if virtue could be reduced to some non-moral property ‘x,’ the question still legitimately remains to be asked, “…but is it virtuous?” 

Moral cognitivism puts forth the thesis mortal statements are bivalent meaning they can be either true or false, and is a response to another group of philosophers who are noncognitivists holding the opposite position that moral statements are not factual propositions so bivalence (truth or falsity) does not apply. Noncognitivists vary in their theories of the speaker’s state of mind, beliefs, and attitudes. The emotivist, as we discussed, claim moral statements are expressions of approval and disapproval; or of a prescription for behavior; or of acceptance of behavioral norms of conduct so in this limited sense moral statements are meaningful yet not bivalent.

 

Other metaethicists adhere to a more severe version of noncognitivist emotivism named the “Error Theory” of moral statements claiming that as linguistic entities they are neither true nor false just as the linguistic moods of wish (optative), hypothetical (subjunctive), or question (interrogative), or the command “Open the door!” (imperative) are not bound by truth-conditional semantics. Ethicist Dr. Kai Nielson writes of the error theory thesis:

 

“…there are some metaethicists who claim that there are objective moral judgments and yet deny that moral judgments…can properly be called true or false. They recognize that moral judgments do not have the kind of necessary truth characteristic of mathematics, and they argue with considerable plausibility that moral statements are not true or false—there are no ethical characteristics, rightness and wrongness, goodness and badness, that are either directly or indirectly observable….’truth’ and ‘falsity’ are not correctly applicable to moral judgments (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 126).”

 

After-Virtue argues, “… the possibility of such rational justification is no longer available. And this is what emotivism denies (AV., p. 19).” However, MacIntyre makes no real effort to distinguish between metaethical philosophers, and fails to see “There are many possible routes to a moral error theory, and one mustn't assume that the metaethical position is refuted if one argumentative strategy in its favor falters (SEP: Moral Antirealism).”

 

Assigning the adjectives of rightness or wrongness to a noun are pseudo-predicates denoting no actual properties and fail as synthetic propositions. However, the moral error theorists are not necessarily eliminativist of moral language, but view “ought” statements as ultimately non-moral. Moral error theorists are epistemic agnostics and still engage with normative language, but remain ethical skeptics. Analytic language philosophers study…language; and as Wittgenstein wrote, “5.6 The limits of my language mean the limits of my world.”  The logical positivist, A.J. Ayer, is credited for this strict error theory version of emotivism, but it was actually suggested to him by philosopher Austin Duncan-Jones that Ayer had forgotten to give credit while “Stephen Satris (1987) tracks the Continental origins of emotivism back to the work of Hermann Lotze in the 19th Century (SEP).”

 

Non-objectivism is, I think, the most interesting metaethical theory, and closest to Wittgenstein’s view on metaethics. Also, non-objectivism exemplifies the same complex entailment relationships between metaethics and normative ethics that was discussed earlier. Non-objectivism is defined as “…moral facts are mind-dependent; here I shall use the term “non-objectivism.” Thus, “moral non-objectivism” denotes the view that moral facts exist and are mind-dependent (Ibid., section 5).”  The question, “What does ‘mind-dependent’ mean?” will be discussed examining epistemological realism and anti-realism, which have their own entailment relations.

 

I believe Wittgenstein’s aphorisms are the result of his summary thoughts on the aporetic character of language itself which we can rediscover in the Tractatus: “This book will perhaps only be understood by those who have themselves already thought the thoughts which are expressed in it—or similar thoughts…(Ibid., p. 23).” Wittgenstein would likely say virtue is not an object, or thing: “4.121 That which expresses itself in language, we cannot express by language.” And in another comment,  “4.1212 What can be shown cannot be said.”  Plato’s aporetic dialogues suggest that "good" cannot be defined algorithmically (Socrates’ geometry lesson): virtue can only be shown. For Wittgenstein, virtue--as a linguistic entity--is not “a thing of this world.” We will discuss further Wittgenstein’s own thoughts on aporia while considering epistemological Realism and Anti-Realism in the second objection to After Virtue


 

MacIntyre’s Critique of Moorean Aporetic Normative Consciousness 

 

…which boils down to ad hominem arguments against Moore and his alias “emotivism.” MacIntyre intended on taking on the voice of Keynes to describe Moore and his Bloomsbury friends when he wrote, “...these people take themselves to be identifying the presence of a nonnatural property, which they call 'good'; but there is in fact no such property and they are doing no more and no other than expressing their feelings and attitudes, disguising the expression of preference and whim by an interpretation of their own utterance and behavior which confers upon it an objectivity that it does not in fact possess (AV. p.17)." However, MacIntyre unconsciously is speaking through the voice of Anytus revealing another bad case of Anytus-itis. Bloomsbury writer Dorothy Parker is quoted saying of the group, "they lived in squares, painted in circles and loved in triangles." So clearly Moore is corrupting the youth! MacIntyre indignantly reports on Bloomsbury’s “private preferences as noncognitivist, aesthetes, and nonnatural that is pretty much correct (Ibid., p. 107). According to After Virtue Moore is giving permission for ethical relativism and sexual anarchy, which we only just now entered this century. It is that the group who were to become Bloomsbury had already accepted the values of Moore's sixth chapter [of Principia Ethica]” (Ibid., p. 15, 16, 18 ).”

 

After Virtue leaps to Rudolf Carnap’s theory of emotivism making no distinctions between Moore, Charles Stevenson, and Ayer’s differing versions. Carnap and Ayer’s versions of noncognitivism were “atypical” according to Dr. Kai Nielsen. Any school, or schools of philosophy can be made into a straw man for easy criticism by interpreting them as hyper-reductionist. In fact, MacIntyre’s account of noncognitivism is historically incomplete. Emotive theory was first presented by Swedish philosopher Axel Hagerstrom in 1917, then later Scandinavian Ingmar Hedenius, and Alf Ross. In the English speaking world I.A. Richards and Bertrand Russell presented emotivism that was further developed by Ayer and Stevenson (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 106). They have all been thrown into the postmodern theory “Boo bucket.”

 

And yet MacIntyre is patient with Callicles of Plato’s dialogue Gorgias for “a systematic statement of his standpoint whatever the deductive consequences and whatever the degree of the breach with ordinary moral usage (AV, p. 140).” Although Moore was not a logical positivist, analytic and ordinary language philosophy developed from his work. According to the history of philosophy historian, Frederick Copleston S.J., “… Moore is concerned with phenomenological rather than a linguistic analysis (Copleston, Vol. 8, part II, p. 409, 415).” In fact, Moore did not have a single methodology, Moore was not a systematic philosopher… Moore's ‘common sense’ is not a system. Even in ethics, where he comes closest to presenting a ‘theory’ he explicitly disavows any aspiration to provide a systematic account of the good. Hence, as the preceding discussions show, Moore's legacy is primarily a collection of arguments, puzzles and challenges (SEP: Moore).”  MacIntyre is so understanding of "Aristotle takes himself not to be inventing an account of the virtues, but to be articulating an account that is implicit in the thought, utterance and action of an educated Athenian (AV. p. 147),” but isn’t this what Moore and his colleagues were doing in trying to develop a “…primary, if incomplete, definition is crucial to the whole enterprise of identifying a core concept of the virtues (Ibid., p. 187)?" Then, within a few pages MacIntyre’s own arguments against analytic philosophy applies the same approach as Moore to define virtue while speaking of “practices” of virtue (Ibid., p. 209)." Dr. Nielsen wrote, “Morality necessarily involves a cluster of practices (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 131)”—bring us back to Wittgenstein whose favorite quote from the poet Goethe is, “In the beginning was the act.” 

“Emotivism is the doctrine that all evaluative judgments and more specifically all moral judgments are nothing but expressions of preference, expressions of attitude or feeling, insofar as they are moral or evaluative in character.”—“After Virtue,” p. 11. 

The emotivists were able to show the various modes of ethical discourse as expression of feelings, imperatives, persuasion, judging, and prescriptions while showing the aporetic question-begging character of understanding rule-governed conduct (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 130). Unfortunately, After Virtue commits the fallacy of one word, one meaning when appealing to Jeremy Bentham’s utilitarianism by equivocating on the words “feeling,” “pain,” and “sensation” with the implicit tri-partite assumption that thought and emotion are inherently oppositional (AV. p. 62). Hegel made the same criticism of Schiermacher’s definition of religion as the feeling for the infinite by confusing--maybe deliberately--the difference between “feeling,” and “sensation,” not recognizing that feeling and thought are both present in emotion.

 

“One of the principal objections adduced by Hegel against Schleiermacher's doctrine of immediate self-consciousness and one that has frequently since been made is that feeling is the lowest grade in the intellectual process, and is not even distinctly human, being also possessed by the brutes as the sense-form of their consciousness. This objection, is itself psychologically false, fails to apprehend Schleiermacher's view, and confounds his representation of sensation with that of feeling. Sensation, it is true, needs to be supplemented by perception and thought: for it is the non-existence, or rather the prophecy of these. It is not so with feeling (Schleiermacher: Personal and Speculative, Robert Munro, Pub. Paisley, Alexander Grardner, 1903, p.200) (pdf.).”

 

After-Virtue attacks the emotive theories of Moore, C.L. Stevenson, A.J. Ayer, R.M. Hare, and F.P. Ramsey by blaming them for the aporetic nature of virtue (AV. p. 17, 206). Even if each of these emotivists is in error, Dr. William P. Alston, University of Chicago notes that “emotive theory has many forms, no one difficulty is likely to be serious for all possible types (Encycl. Vol. 2, p. 496).” In other words, MacIntyre commits the fallacy of composition: a particular emotivist thesis may be in partial error, but the whole can still be correct.  

Anytus Cancel-Culture

After Virtue is explicitly arguing that emotivist noncognitivism is undermining all normative ethics by reducing moral statements to caprice; consequently, Moore’s Bloomsbury aestheticism is immoral: “…Moore's disciples advanced their private preferences under the cover of identifying the presence or absence of a non-rational property of goodness, a property which was in fact a fiction…(AV. p. 33, 107)." First, Moore is in fact a cognitivist, nonnaturalist, but his case against naturalism drew other philosophers to noncognitivism (Wikiemotivism), and (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 100). Secondly, the criticism of Moore’s ethical character confuses metaethics with normative ethics: “…any form of noncognitivism would in effect undermine the objectivity of moral judgments…to take the remark in this way is to confuse metaethical claims with normative ethical ones (Encycl. Vol. 3, p. 130). 

So let’s look at the positive characteristics not of Moore, but of Ludwig Wittgenstein who ranks with the terrible nonnaturalistic, noncognitivist, non-objectivist ethicists. Wittgenstein was closest to John Maynard Keynes, but was not an enthusiastic member of the Bloomsbury literary circle. Instead, he attended few of the Society’s meetings; he was not a native speaker of English, and had an ascetic personality detesting small talk at social gatherings (Ray Monk, “Wittgenstein: Duty of Genius,” (1990) Free Press, p. 256).  Wittgenstein came from an immensely wealthy family; his father was an Austria-Hungarian steel magnate who in 1913 left his fortune to his son Ludwig who shocked his banker and family by giving his fortune away to artists, and poets. When the Nazis invaded Austria-Hungary they seized the Wittgenstein family estate fortune that only had seven tons of gold remaining. Wittgenstein read Leo Tolstoy’s “The Gospel in Brief” which had a profound influence on his life and became a devoted Christian mystic (B. McGuinness, “Wittgenstein: A Life,”(1988 ), Univ. Cal. Press, p. 220). In 1913 Wittgenstein joined with Keynes to secretly funnel donated money through King’s College to increase the yearly stipend for the once famous logician W.E. Johnson living in near poverty (Ibid., 99). 

During World War I in 1915, Italy declared war on Austria-Hungry. Wittgenstein volunteered for the most dangerous job as an assisting enemy artillery position spotter. His job was to shine a spotlight on enemy artillery positions causing retaliating counter-artillery fire. The Austrian military lost some 100,000 men in battle (Ibid., p. 263). Wittgenstein was awarded at least three war metals: the Silver Medal of Valour, a Bronze Metal, and the Band of the Military Service Medal with Swords (Ibid., p 242, 258, 263). After the Italians defeated the Austrian army at Vittorio Veneto, Italy, ranked Austrian officers fled abandoning their own retreating troops who were refusing to fight; but Wittgenstein stayed behind and was captured by Italian forces in November 1918 in Northern Italy at Trentino. He subsequently spent nine months in Italian prisoner of war camps: a total of 300,000 prisoners were captured with 30,000 dying in captivity (Ibid., p. 267-8 ). 

The point is Wittgenstein was not a nihilist, nor even an ethical skeptic; his famous work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922) was not just about logic, but a book on ethics. His telos was to preserve in modern society what is most important in life--that which cannot be said, but only shown. For Wittgenstein, logic is ethics! This view is not original, but can at least be traced to philosopher Wilhelm Windelband (1848-1915) of the Baden School of neo-Kantianism which emphasized the study of culture, ethics, and aesthetics describes the axiological similarity of logic and ethical reasoning: 

"For just as ethics is concerned with moral values, so is logic concerned with a value, namely truth… The true is that which ought to be thought. Thus all logical thought is guided by a value, a norm. The ultimate axioms of logic cannot be proved; but we must accept them if we value truth. And we must accept truth as an objective norm or value unless we are prepared to reject all logical thinking. (Copleston, Vol. 7, pdf. p. 749/ original pagination p. 364)." 

Philosophically it has always been “After Virtue” in the sense that normative ethics and metaethics have always encountered ethical skepticism, nihilism, and relativism of which Socrates was accused of and executed by the state. Meno’s dogmatic realist friend, Anytus, who voted for Socrates’ death is still with us today, but in the contemporary form of crusaders against “postmodern relativism. 

The Weberian Hip-bone…  

After Virtue sets it sights next on anti-positivist sociologist Max Weber as responsible for justifying the new bureaucratic state, "I am referring precisely to his [Weber] account of how managerial authority is justified in bureaucracies (AV., p. 26, 86, 114)." This is the most puzzling criticism of MacIntyre that connects Weber to the emotivist bone, that’s connected to the relativist bone, that’s connected to the prescriptivist persuasive bone, connected to the individualist manipulative bureaucratic state bone, that connects to the Frankfurt School leg-bone (Ibid., p. 31). MacIntyre directs his criticism of Weber’s attempt to “define authority naturalistically,” combined with stochastic studies of how a group will obey commands. Weber defined three forms of authority in society: traditional, rational, and charismatic. As a sociologist, and historian he studied legal history, and Roman agrarian law; one can see why Weber would be interested in the topic of authority, but some critics blaming Weber for the rise of the authoritarian state is beyond absurd.  

Weber’s list of written work is short because of his early death in 1920 from the Spanish flu. The anti-positivist sociologist attempted to study society, “…through interpretive (rather than purely empiricist) methods, based on understanding the purpose and meanings that individuals attach to their own actions...His analysis of modernity and rationalisation would significantly influence the critical theory associated with the Frankfurt School “(WikiWeber)." Weber wrote that modern society is “characterised by rationalisation and intellectualisation and, above all, by the ‘disenchantment of the world’ (Ibid., fn, 69).“ 

…Is Connected to the Frankfurt Leg-bone 

MacIntyre’s own criticism of disenchanted modernism (anomie) could of been taken right from Weber’s research; in fact, their criticism can be traced back to the Frankfurt School of Social Research. Long before After Virtue was written, the Frankfurt Schools produced a mass of literature that critique modern naturalist-positivist scientific reductionalism. Let’s take for example the Frankfurt school philosopher Herbert Marcuse’s assessment of modern scientific ideology in “One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society (1964)(pdf.) focusing attention on the Orwellian decay of language resulting in a universal “withering,” or constriction of non-reified experience, and fiercely critiques ahistorical positivist analytic linguistic philosophy in particular!  Another book, “Eclipse of Reason,”(1947) authored by the director of the Frankfurt school, Max Horkheimer, is an anti-Enlightenment critique of instrumental reason. In another critique of modernism “The Dialectic of Enlightenment,”(1944-47) authored by Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno examine instrumental-pragmatic scientific operationalism concerned only with the efficient control of means and critical of Wittgenstein’s early logical positivism as they interpreted the Tractatus. “The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy,” (1954) by Edmond Husserl is criticism of modern epistemological mechanistic scientization of life, and worked out the concept of the pre-theoretical “Lifeworld” structures of culture, society, and personality. And most importantly, Soren Kierkegaard’s 1846 “Concluding Unscientific Postscript,” by Soren Kierkegaard, trans. by David F. Swenson and Walter Lowrie, 1941, Princeton Univer. Press (pdf.)(Hereafter, ‘Postscript’). Kierkegaard wrote, "In the end all corruption will come about as a consequence of the natural sciences...(Kierkegaard, Journal: VII A 186, 187-200 year 1853 in Postscript, p. xv).” Some acknowledgment should be given to critical theory for its contribution to the critique of Enlightenment—because the Weberian hip-bone is connected to the Frankfurt leg-bone. 

The most annoying distortion of the postmodern critics is this: some postmodern critics accuse the Frankfurt school of lacking the very insights that they were famous for formulating. It’s like accusing Plato of misunderstanding the Platonic Socrates. The postmodernist critics attack the Frankfurt school with the very same arguments that the Frankfurt school is known to have formulated—they chew up the school’s critiques of modern industrial ideology, and spit them out partially digested to their readers. Postmodernist critics completely ignore the earlier “traditions” by failing to understand that modern scholars originated many of the epistemic criticisms that focus on society’s scientific and moral malaise that the traditionalist only complain about—without using the word “existentialism”—such as the objectivating attitude of instrumental reason, scientism, alienation, nihilism, anomie, relativism, disenchanted experience, authoritarianism, and acquisitive hyper-individualism (AV., p.33, 88, 137). Kant, Hegel, Marx, Marcuse, Horkheimer, Adorno, Weber, and Wittgenstein all addressed these issues, and did it much better.

...next:
Second Counter-Argument: MacIntyre as an Aristotelian-Thomist Realist contradictorily embraces Anti-realist Epistemology.

Appendix G, Part I of V: Postmodern Socrates on Virtue



Postmodern Socrates on Virtue

“The fact is that far from knowing whether it can be taught, I have no idea what virtue is…Not only that, you may say also that, to the best of my belief, I have never met anyone who did know.”—Socrates in Plato’s dialogue, Meno, (pdf.), para. 71 and 71c.

“My advice to you, if you will listen to it, is to be careful.”
—Anytus to Socrates, Meno, para. 94e.

 

Introduction:

Of all of the major areas of study in philosophy--epistemology, metaphysics, and ethics (some would include the history of philosophy)—ethics is by far the most difficult and complex to analyze as ethical discourse incorporates historical beliefs, metaphysical assumptions, and normative ethical rules (what one ought to do). Notice that the word discourse has already biased this introduction by focusing on the examination of moral language such as the terms “good,” “better,” “obligation,” “wrong,” “right” and “virtue.” Integration by individuals of different worldviews, cultural moral concepts, and the rational justifications of moral actions make the use of normative ethical terms the obvious area for the philosophy of language to investigate with its applied methodology of logical analysis. There is an apparent parallelism, which we will investigate, between ethics and epistemology that is productive for clarifying ethical concepts until the meaning of some key terms become obscure and even irresolvable as various logical analyses inevitably separate into different seemingly contradictory camps of thought. 

The motive and purpose of this essay is to once again critique the ubiquitous trope (meaning “twist”) of “postmodernism.” Rhetorically, a trope is parasitical of some original meaning of a word, or theme, which is then used in a different sense that further degrades into a cliché like, for example, the “absent-minded professor,” as a fictional story character. Postmodernism is a collection of pre-selected philosophical disputes from the history of Western philosophy that are reinterpreted as somehow “new,” and representative of a contemporary existential threat to Western civilization organized by conspiratorial homunculi allied with deviant minions such as leftists, socialists, Marxists, dirty hippies, and romance novelist Jane Austen who understands “the virtues is a certain kind of marriage and indeed a certain kind of naval officer (that is, a certain kind of English naval officer)(AV., p. 186)” to promote a false ideology that denies the existence of all virtue, truth, and knowledge (Postmodernism and Faith, video). 

During the last few years a number of persons have recommended that I read Dr. Alasdair MacIntyre’s work on ethics entitled, “After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory,”(1981)(pdf.)(Abbreviated as AV). I chose to critique this particular book since Dr. MacIntyre can actually formulate arguments of his critique of postmodernism unlike those embarrassing self-described postmodern critics hanging around the Internet. MacIntyre published in his early career many academic articles on Marxism (MacIntyre bibliography) so he is sui generis, in a category of his own, separate from the media’s fast-talking former Marxists who couldn’t tell the difference between Karl Marx, and Carl B. Marks. He authored After Virtue at about the same time Neoliberalism swept over the Untied States in the form of Reagan’s cultural revolution of 1981: a Great March forward into despotism. MacIntyre used the term “postmodernist,” only once in “After-Virtue,(AV., p. XII) along with other terms such as “Enlightenment project,” (Ibid., p. 36), “post-Enlightenment culture,” (Ibid., p. 113), “modern culture,” “modern age,” and “modernity.”  In another book, “Whose Justice? Which Rationality?” (1988 )(pdf.)(WJWR), MacIntyre continues his extended argument with “post-Enlightenment culture,” (WJWR, p. 6) “postmodern relativists,” (Ibid., p. 353), and “postmodernist radicals, (Ibid., p. 387). All of these terms have the same meaning and are used interchangeably by postmodern critics. 

In the prologue of the third edition of After Virtue (2007) titled, “After Virtue after a Quarter of a Century,” MacIntyre writes of his personal beliefs [My bracket]: "When I wrote After Virtue, I was already an Aristotelian, but not yet a Thomist, something made plain in my account of Aquinas at the end of chapter 13 [Medieval Aspects and Occasions]. I became a Thomist after writing After Virtue in part because I became convinced that Aquinas was in some respects a better Aristotelian than Aristotle, that not only was he an excellent interpreter of Aristotle's texts, but that he had been able to extend and deepen both Aristotle’s metaphysical and his moral enquiries (p. X)." 

MacIntyre’s stated philosophical worldview can be accurately described as Aristotelian-Thomist Realism: “MacIntyre defends Thomistic realism as rational enquiry directed to the discovery of truth (IEP: MacIntyre).” I did not choose MacIntyre’s book for this critical essay because of any Catholic belief he may, or may not have. There are a number of Catholic based ethical philosophies that are admirable such as the Trappist Monk Thomas Merton advocated, but was murdered after he gave an anti-war speech in 1968 against the Vietnam War at the International Asiatic Conference in Thailand. Also, Pope John Paul II studied Phenomenologist, Max Scheler, and advocates a very interesting version of phenomenological Thomism resulting in the Pope’s dissertation titled "Reevaluation of the possibility of founding a Catholic ethic on the ethical system of Max Scheler.” Dorothy Day represents another case in which this religious tradition is recognized as consistent with labor activism that values human beings, and inspired her to help create the Catholic Worker Movement. The Church awarded the title “Servant of God“ to Day and was positively mentioned by the very popular Pope Francis in 2015. My focus of concern here is not Catholicism, but rather the philosophical incoherence of the postmodern trope I have described. 

Dr. MacIntyre is difficult to critique for three reasons. First, he has authored a massive number of books and articles during his lifetime. Since I have only one lifetime, and unable to read all of his writings, I will have to be satisfied with a parity check for possible incoherence of his relevant views on virtue. After Virtue conceptually contains in substance many of his most important philosophical writings, and themes. For example, his journal article, “Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science,” (1977)(pdf.)(abbreviation, EC)  is recapitulated in “After Virtue: Chapter Seven: 'Fact', Explanation and Expertise.” 

Secondly, MacIntyre is a masterful rhetorician and his writing is among the best a person can read in the English language. His training in Aristotelian philosophy shows through his artfully crafted written words and arguments: each sentence is packed with meaning in a complex chain of other arguments that make it a challenge to construct clear and concise corresponding counter-arguments. This highly intelligent philosopher is also a skillful escape artist who is difficult to pin down on some points as he anticipates potential criticism while moving strategically in and around the complicated passages of Aristotle’s taxonomy of virtue. After-Virtue is complex as MacIntyre dives into ancient philosophy, Western Medieval thought, and modern British analytic language philosophy. 

Lastly, MacIntyre’s After Virtue is difficult to critique because there are certain argument threads that I agree with, but which are entangled with other postmodern critiques that I found logically problematic. Some of the topics that I thought were very good and learned from are the following: his very short summary of Kierkegaard is very good short summary (AV., p. 39); his critique of modern social sciences and modern inductive methodologies (Ibid., p. 88 ); Homer’s heroic poetry of the Iliad and Socrates on Homeric ethics (Ibid., p. 121, 131); the Virtues of Athens chapter gave criticism of ideological individualism and emphasized the need for friendship and community instead of promoting Pleonexia, or excessive greed, and acquisitiveness (Ibid., p. 137, 208, 214, 227); the importance of Narrative for social life (Ibid., p. 137, 227); dominance of the modern bureaucratic manager model with a critique of work in modern society (Ibid., p. 228 ); examined Phronesis, or the ability to exercise good intellectual judgment as a virtue (Ibid., p. 154); criticism of imperialism, or original acquisition (Ibid., p.251). I generally accept MacIntyre’s expertise in After-Virtue regarding the doctrines Aristotelian and Thomistic. 

There are some problematic issues with weaving a critique of postmodernism into this study of virtue, but I want to be open about the criteria used in formulating my criticisms of the many complex arguments MacIntyre presents so that my reasoning can be followed. I am keeping in mind three philosophers as my philosophical touchstones: Logician Ludwig Wittgenstein (mostly his later thought), Transcendental Kantian criticism, and existentialist Soren Kierkegaard. Wittgenstein studied both Kant and Kierkegaard very closely, and deeply influenced his study of philosophy. 

Within this essay are four major counter-arguments directed toward MacIntyre’s definition and criticisms of postmodernism: 

  1. If consistently applied, MacIntyre’s view of postmodernism defines the premodern  philosopher, Socrates, as postmodern.
  2. MacIntyre as an Aristotelian-Thomist Realist contradictorily embraces Anti-realist epistemology.
  3. MacIntyre leaves the door open for Relativistic Historicism while advocating a particular tradition of ethical thought.
  4. MacIntyre’s viewpoint is subject to Ethical Skepticism compounded by 2 and 3.


 

First Counter-argument: “Postmodern” Socrates 

 

“In my opinion you are well advised not to leave Athens and live abroad. If you behaved like this as a foreigner in another country, you would most likely be arrested as a wizard.”—Meno to Socrates, 80b. 

I.F. Stone directs our attention to the word “wizard,” or "γόης(goes) that Meno used to describe Socrates as “one who howls out enchantments, a sorcerer,” and metaphorically a “juggler”, or “cheat,” and “imposter” (I.F. Stone, “The Trial of Socrates,”(1988 ), Little, Brown & Co., Boston, p. 59). Western philosophical literature on ethics is at least as old as the Epic of Gilgamesh, an ancient epic poem authored about 3000 BC. The ideal arena for our purposes of discussion is Plato’s famous dialogue, the Meno, since it contains fundamental problems of ethics that can bring together the thoughts of philosophers such as MacIntyre, G.E. Moore, Kierkegaard, and Wittgenstein for examination. 

My guiding touchstones for reading After Virtue are interestingly related. For MacIntyre, English philosopher G.E. Moore is exhibit “A” of the folly of postmodernism, while Kierkegaard’s corpse is presented as exhibit “B” of the ravages of modernist disease. MacIntyre does not mention Wittgenstein in After Virtue, but Wittgenstein and G.E. Moore were both contemporary professors at Trinity College, Cambridge along with Bertrand Russell. G.E. Moore, who was at one time president of the Aristotelian Society at Cambridge, is recognized as one of the early founders of analytic language philosophy. The School of Logical Positivism known as the “Vienna Circle” (1924) was founded in the name of Wittgenstein for his philosophical work, “Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus” (1921)(pdf.), before he was discovered by the positivists to be a radical mystic. Although Wittgenstein did not have a high regard for Moore as a philosopher, he was influenced by Moore’s view on ethics, which will be noted. 

The Meno dialogue contains ethical problems by which we can categorize various normative views on virtue in order to interpret their ethical (what ought to be) and metaethical (what is) standpoints; then, identify them by classificatory scheme as a cognitivist, noncognitivist, naturalist, nonnaturalist, objectivist, non-objectivist, anti-realist and/or realist. We will kindly consider objections to our Procrustean classifications, which might be raised by passionate disciples that do not like being pigeonholed. This approach provides a common referential framework to explore these ever-elusive ethical dilemmas, and will strengthen all four objections against MacIntyre’s criticisms of modernism. 

A Very Short Background on the Socratic Dialogue, Meno: “On Virtue” 

MacIntyre dates the Meno dialogue during Plato’s late period of authorship (WJWR, p. 63). The Meno is a fictional dialogue written by Plato in 385 B.C. about real historical persons and events during 402 B.C.  which is about three years before the trial of Socrates. Ancient scholars later subtitled this dialogue as “On Virtue” as a sequel to the Protagoras dialogue wherein Socrates claims that virtue is knowledge; therefore, it must be something teachable (I.F. Stone, p. 52-68 ). During this period Athens was just emerging from a terrible dictatorship and civil war. Beginning back in 490 B.C. to 480 B.C. Athens and Sparta had successfully combined forces to oppose and repel the Persian invasion of Greece. However, later in 430 BC, Sparta declared war against it former ally, Athens, for breaking a peace treaty and began a long series of battles called the Peloponnesian Wars. Also, this was the time that a reoccurring Typhus plague begins in Athens that killed about 100,000 Athenians as Sparta laid siege against the crowded fortified city. Finally, the Peloponnesian wars between Athens and Sparta ended with the defeat of Athens at Aigospotamoi.

 

Years later in 404 B.C. the “Rule of the Thirty Tyrants” begins supported by Athenian oligarchs treasonously allying themselves with Sparta. Just prior to the events in the dialogue Meno, Spartan rulers were thinking about murdering all the Athenian men and enslaving everyone else, but then on reflection thought it more profitable to establish an oligarchy backed by the wealthy Athenian aristocracy of which Socrates had some distance family relations. During the régime’s short eight months reign, the Thirty were able to torture and execute without trial at least 1500 Athenians thought to be democratic subversives, and hired 300 "lash-bearers" to whip the Athenians to instill collective fear of the regime. Plato recounts in the Apology dialogue how the Thirty ordered him and four men to capture and execute an Athenian citizen named Leon of Salamis. Plato provides an interesting explanation for the Thirty’s execution orders and why so many Greeks were executed: “…they issued such instructions, their object being to implicate as many people as possible in their crimes (32c-d).” This is a history Americans should remember even today as right-wing fascists encourage election fraud and violent insurrection. Socrates was also ordered by the Tyrants to commit the same crime of execution as Plato was asked to do, but just laughed: both philosophers refused to cooperate putting their lives in great danger.

 

And then the tables turned. Belligerent former democratic forces of Athens in May 403 B.C. defeated the Thirty Tyrants and their military henchmen. The events in the Meno occurred in “late January, or early February 402 B.C. (IEP: Meno).” The atmosphere was politically very tense while Athenian pro-democratic leaders were negotiating with the oligarchs an amnesty for crimes committed during the former tyrannical régime-- except for the Thirty themselves and about 3,000 officials who were not to be spared punishment. Two of the Thirty were a cousin and uncle related to Socrates. And then one last outrage committed by the oligarchs was to massacre the people in the town of Eleusis, and then used the city as a base from which followed yet another insurrectionist attack against Athens in 401 B.C. that brought about the Tyrant’s final defeat by Athens.

 

This is the history that Plato knows from lived experience and set Socrates speaking to Meno, and the unhappy Anytus about virtue. The formerly leading moderate demos politician, Anytus, had to pay a bribe to the Thirty’s court that cost him all of his wealth as the owner of a tannery (I.F, Stone, p. 174-180). While writing the Meno, Plato knew that in 399 B.C. Socrates would be executed partly due to Anytus’ guilty vote at his trial. There are many stories of Anytus’ demise; they are all contradictory, and none of them have happy endings. Plato also knew that the mercenary soldier, Meno, was to join the soon defeated Persian army of Cyrus who was attempting to overthrow his own brother, King Artaxerxes II. Cyrus’ defeated enemy commanders were beheaded--except for Meno who was so hated for his greed for wealth and power that he instead suffered prolonged torture before finally being executed (IEP:Meno). I.F. Stone comments that during early antiquity there was not a clear distinction between trade and war (I.F.Stone, p. 26).

 

During this setting of simmering civil war and gratuitous executions, Socrates appears in Athens asking, “What is virtue?” I.F. Stone reminds us virtue, or “ἀρετή,” (Arête) is derived from the name of the Greek god of war Ares, whose Roman name is Mars. Virtue was believed to be goodness and excellence, which meant to the Greeks “machismo, manliness, valor, and prowess.” “Virtue” is from the Latin term “vitus” or “life”. If virtue were knowledge, it would include the mercenary’s training in military weaponry and actual war experience (Ibid., p. 52). Socrates noted that Cleophantes, the son of the highly respected Athenian Themistocoles, “was well trained in horsemanship that he could stand upright on a horseback and throw a javelin from that position, and many other wonderful accomplishments the young man had, for his father had him taught and made expert in every skill that a good instructor could impart (Meno, 93d).

 

The Poverty of Philosophy…of Ethics

 “The fact is that far form knowing whether it can be taught, I have no idea what virtue itself is. That is my own case. I share the poverty of my fellow countrymen in this respect….”—Socrates in the Meno (71a). 

Plato’s dialogues can be read on multiple levels: the philosophical problems discussed; logical structure; dialogue storyline narrative; the characters and their interactions with other participants. One can read for Plato’s sarcastic humor, “But look, Meno, here’s a piece of luck. Anytus has just sat down beside us (90a),” or when Socrates complains of his bad memory (Meno, 70c, 76b) just before introducing his Theory of Recollection. And interestingly, another level of interpretation is Plato’s beliefs as compared to Socrates’ views on the theme of each dialogue. This is especially difficult since there are no surviving writings by Socrates except for student lecture notes; in addition, it is especially difficult when the dialogue such as the Meno ends in no firm conclusion about what virtue is. Socrates held to the theory knowledge as remembrance, but Plato later seems to give it up. All students should remember to take good notes! 

Ancient scholars have named the early Platonic dialogues as the Aporetic dialogues which include the following works: Apology, Critias, Euthydemus, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Laches, Lysis, Protagoras, and Meno. There is debate on some of the dialogue classifications as early. MacIntyre for example places the Meno in the late period of authorship, while some others place it in the early late period. The Greek term “ἀπορίᾳ” when translated with reference to place means “difficulty of passing.” “πορίᾳ” without an alpha “” means a “pathway,” but combined with the letter “ἀ” a negative prefix (alpha privative) changes the meaning to “no pathway, or “no way out.” However, when applied to persons, aporia means “poverty,” and this is Socrates’ metaphor for the Athenians’ inability to define virtue (Meno, 71b). In the Meno, Plato makes use of a method of argument known as the “Elenchus,” or ἔλεγξις meaning, “refuting,’ or “reproving,” and is the Socratic method of deriving a contradiction by having the speaker go through cross-examination and argumentation to eventually agree with a conclusion that is directly opposite to their originally held beliefs. Socrates does this multiple times in discourse with Meno on virtue (73e, 78b, 80a). 


Woke Socrates

“The unexamined life is not worth living.”-Socrates, Apology (38a)


This section will summarize the Meno (pdf. with Stephanus pagination!) dialogue’s logical structure for later argument analysis. 

Meno begins asking if virtue can be taught (70a). Socrates in turn asks Meno to define virtue, but Meno instead gives a list of different kinds of virtues such as the good management of city affairs; to help his friends and harm their foes; a woman’s obedience and household management; and other virtues for children, old men, slaves, and freemen (71e). Notice Meno’s list of virtues is about conduct. Socrates objects to Meno’s attempt to simply list virtues, but instead he wants the essence, or universal property of virtue, and not individual virtues (72b). Socrates introduced the analogies of Bees (72b), shape (73e), and color (74d) in asking Meno to not describe what bees, shapes, and colors are in particular, but what is a bee in general, or what shape, or color are in themselves. Socrates is focused on finding a definition of virtue in ethical discourse.

Search for Essences

Within Husserlian phenomenology the method for defining an essence is called Eidetic Reduction where by a concept, or some experience, or a phenomenon is varied by observation, and imagination to derive its universal property, or essence in formulating a clear meaning. “Eidetic” is from Greek, εἶδος, (eidos), meaning “that which is seen, form, shape, or  figure.”​ Socrates refers specifically to shapePhenomenological reduction is the method where by the phenomenologist strips away, or omits all the accidental attributes of a phenomenon, and leaves only the necessary attributes known as its “essence.” Words are essences, and from them we formulate definitions. Phenomenology is the most extreme version of empiricism, but even with this radical empiricism notice that the “negative act” of “omission” of accidental attributes is an indispensable step for determining essence. (Philosophy of Symbolic Forms: Phenomenology of Knowledge, E. Cassirer, 1957, Vol. III, p.193)(pdf.). 

Socrates questions Meno for another definition that is singular and universal such as his friend Gorgias’ views on virtue (73d). One quality, according to Gorgias, is the ability to govern men. Socrates objects again arguing this definition should not apply to slaves, or a child so both agree to add “justice as a virtue.” Socrates gives further objections reminding Meno they are looking for the whole of virtue, and not parts of virtue (73e). Meno’s next attempt defines virtue as desiring fine things and being able to acquire them (77b).  Socrates seizes on the term “desire.” Meno believes men do desire evil things (77c) even if it is evil, but then recants after Socrates convinces him that no person desires evil since it brings injury and unhappiness to themselves (78b); maybe not Socrates strongest argument. Socrates does not consider it to be virtuous if someone acquires good things unjustly; rather, justice, temperance, or piety, or some other attribute of virtue must be connected to acquisition if we are to consider it virtuous (78e). But again Socrates reminds Meno they want the whole of virtue, and agreed they cannot define it in terms of its parts! So they must go back to the beginning of their inquiry (79c). 

Geometry and Virtue

At this point the discussion turns to Meno’s dilemma of how could someone recognize something unknown that is being sought after (80d). As a phenomenological experiment Socrates asks a slave a series of simple geometry questions to demonstrate innate, or a prior knowledge (82a-86a). Notice Socrates’ theory of innate knowledge is based on the subjective experience of calculative thinking in making an inference to a conclusion that is phenomenologically similar to the subjective experience of remembering. Later on we will see how the phenomenological method of description is important to G.E. Moore’s analysis of ethical discourse and is completely missed by his critics—including Wittgenstein. Socrates’ experiment is also making a comparison between answering geometric questions and seeking answers about virtue. Unlike the confused Meno and Anytus, the slave is much more successful answering Socrates’ geometry questions. 

Socrates will return to Meno’s dilemma later in the dialogue, but now he wants to explore the hypothesis of what attribute of the soul must exist if it can be taught (87b). Virtue is good and so it is also advantageous (87e) unlike the attributes of health, strength, good looks, or wealth that could do us harm if not used wisely. When guided by wisdom—not ignorance—the advantages of courage, temperance, wit, and memory will bring happiness (88c). Consequently, virtue must be some kind of knowing and not by some innate nature (89a). Socrates proposes a second hypothesis: if something were teachable, there would be teachers and students (89d).  However, Socrates says he has not found any teachers of virtue (89d). 

A Bad Case of Homunculus Anytus-itis 

The financially bankrupted Anytus joins the discussion with Socrates and is asked if he found any teachers of virtue like, for example, the sophist (89e) to which Anytus strongly rejects declaring he would have nothing to do with such folks since any Athenian gentleman is a better man than any of them (91c). Anytus believed that a group of foreigners and other undesirables were under-minding the Athenian polis by questioning its tradition of virtue ethics, and Greek divinities (atheism). Socrates responds that one can be a good man and not a good teacher of virtue; take for example, the sons of some of the best men of Athens. If virtue could be taught, they would have passed it to their children. This comment angers Anytus thinking that Socrates is referring to him and his friends: "I think, Socrates, that you readily speak ill of men. I would advise you, if you are willing to listen to me, to be discreet. As is probably the case in other cities, it is easier to do men harm than good, and certainly in this one. But I think you already know that (94e)." Socrates continues his argument: if there are no teachers, there can be no students (96b). 

Socratic Aporia 

Socrates now answers Meno’s dilemma of trying to identify something, such as virtue, that seems to have no agreed definition. Socrates claims knowledge for the purpose of acting rightly is not the only source of virtue; true opinion could also lead to virtue just as a person who never traveled the road to Larissa could guide others just as well an experienced guide with knowledge. Meno counters that true opinion is not certain for making judgments. Socrates responds that true opinion must be “tied down” by reason to determine if an opinion is true. In this particular dialogue knowledge is a justified true belief that separates it from true opinion, and that an inexperienced traveler “…will be just as good a guide, believing in the truth but not knowing it (97b).” Both knowledge and true opinion are acquired by experience, but not given by nature (98d). This is Socrates’ answer to Meno’s paradox: investigation, and reason can identify the unknown. Socrates is asked again if virtue is a matter of teaching, but argues against his own hypothesis (Virtue is knowledge) by proposing if virtue was a matter of teaching, it would also have to be knowledge, and then there would be teachers of virtue. However, there are no teachers of virtue. Therefore, it is not the case virtue is a matter of teaching and that it is knowledge so they can no longer believe virtue is a kind of knowledge (99b). And yet, there are wise leaders of the city not because of their knowledge, but from divine inspiration like that granted to the Greek poets and oracles. But, we still do not know what virtue really is in itself–in essence (100b).


The Logic of Meno

A four legged cow is a cow”—Bertand Russell


I want to use the same logical symbolism introduced in the essay, “Bertrand Russell's Critique of Fregean Logico-Mathematical Objects,” to examine the difficulties of defining the concept of virtue exemplified in the Meno dialogue. The logician I.M. Copi worked out in his textbook, “Symbolic Logic: Fourth edition” (1973), p. 150, the symbolic conventions for representing attributes of a thing, and the attributes of attributes. 

Let the attributes of a thing be symbolized as F 

An attribute of individual things =F

Some Attributes = (∃F)

All attributes = (F) 

The essay on mathematical objects logically demonstrates how attributes of attributes must be separated (Ramified Type Theory) from attributes (x is truthful) and attributes of attributes (truthfulness is a virtue); otherwise, the symbolism becomes contradictory (Russell’s Paradox). “Ramified” is from Latin that means “branches,” or in this case branches of multi-purpose meanings of the word “virtue” as defined by Meno. I learned from MacIntyre himself that “there is no single, central, core conception of the virtues (AV., p. 186, 187)”; also, there is a “problem of multiple sets of virtues: "set of virtues: friendship, courage, self-restraint, wisdom, justice (AV., p. 134).” For example, there are the four cardinal virtues of justice, prudence, temperance, and courage (AV., p. 167). There are also theological virtues such as faith, hope, and charity (AV., p. 168 ). This is known as “the problem of the unity of virtues…(AV., p. 179).” When asked what virtue is Meno gives an entire list of core virtues (72b). Socrates did not want properties of virtue (shapes of virtue), but rather a definition of virtue itself (What is shape itself?). 

If we mix attributes with “attributes of attributes,” we commit The fallacy of Μετάβασις εἰς ἄλλο γένος, or “switching to a different genus” there is a danger of deriving a contradiction since “Where the meta-base is not explicitly made as an analogy, it leads to a sudden leap in a line of argument or argument in which one incorrectly no longer treats the original object of the argument but a completely different one.” 

And so we must add another rule: attribute of attributes is symbolized in boldface italic capital letters ‘A’,’B’. ‘C’,….’Z’ 

Now our logical symbolism enables us to state the following atomic propositions, and many more in principle, without contradiction.

 Ux : x is Unpunctual

Tx : x is Truthful

VFF is a Virtue

FF : F is a Fault

GFF is Good

FU :Unpunctuality is a Fault

UFF is Useful

DFF is Desirable

VT :Truthfulness is a Virtue

VC: Courage is a Virtue 

We must keep in mind the distinction between goods things and good conduct, and whether they share the same most universal properties that can be found in any particular instance of virtue; but we must define virtue first in order to do any systematic categorization. 

Moore would say that virtue is a “simple” notion that cannot be defined; we can define complex notions since they can be described by listing its properties; a horse for example, until the parts can no longer be defined. By “undefined” he means, “there is nothing whatsoever which we could so substitute for good; and that is what I mean, when I say that good is indefinable (“Principia Ethica” (1903)(pdf.) para. 8  ).” 

Examples of propositions in symbolic form:

(F)(UF DF)
(All useful attributes are desirable.)

(∃F)(DF⊃ ~UF)
(Some desirable attributes are not useful.)

 …or more complex compound propositions:

(x){[Mx * (F)(VF Fx)] ⊃ Vx} * (∃x)[(Mx *Vx) * (∃F)(V*~Fx)]
(A man who possesses all virtues is a virtuous man, but there are virtuous men who do not possess all virtue.)

Definitions:

Vx: x is virtuous
Mx: x is a man
(F): For all attributes
VF: F is a virtue
(∃F): For at least one attribute
(∃x): For at least one x
(x): For all x
⊃ : If, then conditional statement
* : and
~ : negation

Socrates argues that if virtue was a matter of teaching, it would also have to be knowledge, and then there would be teachers of virtue. However, there are no teachers of virtue. Therefore, it is not the case virtue is a matter of teaching and that it is knowledge so they can no longer believe virtue is a kind of knowledge (99b). 

Socrates’ argument in symbolic form: 

1.)  (x){[(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx] ⊃ (∃y)(Hy)}

For any x, if all virtue is teachable, then virtue is knowledge; then there is at least one teacher of virtue. 

2.)  (y)~(Hy)

There are no teachers of virtue.
___________________________________________

3.)  ~ [(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx]

Therefore, virtue is not teachable, nor is it knowledge.


Formal Proof is the following: 

1)    (x){[(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx] ⊃ (∃y)(Hy)} 

2)    (y)~(Hy)                                         /:: (x) ~[(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx]

________________________________________________

3)    [(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx] ⊃ (∃y)(Hy) ..........1, Universal Instantiation 

4)    ~(∃y)(Hy) ......................................2, Equivalence 

5)    ~ [(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx] .........................3, 4, Modus Tollens 

6)    (x) ~[(Vx * Tx) ⊃ Kx]......................5, Universal Generalization


Variable Definitions and Rules:

V = virtue
T = virtue is teachable
K = knowledge
H = teachers of virtue
/:: = therefore
≡ = Equivalent truth value

Quantification operators:

(x)Φx ≡ Everything is
~(x)Φx ≡ Nothing is
(∃x)Φx ≡ Something is
~(∃x)Φx ≡ Something is not 

Equivalence of quantification operators with negation symbol:

(x)Φx ≡ ~(∃x)~Φx
(∃x)Φx ≡ ~(x)~Φx
(x)~Φx ≡ ~(∃x)Φx
(∃x)~Φ ≡ ~(x)Φx 

I am always looking for tautologies such as “A one legged cow is a cow.” Let’s symbolize “Good Swiss watch,” as (G * W), or expressed in predicate logic as: 

GW ≡ (∃x)(Gx * Wx)
(Some good Swiss watch)

1)    (∃x)(Gx * Wx) 

2)    Gy * Wy .....1, Existential Instantiation: “y” is unknown, or ambiguous name. 

3)    Gy ..............2, Simplification 

/:: (∃x)(Gx) ........3, Existential Generalization


In other words,
 

(G * W) ⊃ G
( If G and W; then, G)

…. which is a tautology that can be repeated tirelessly with other attributes D, E, F, G, ect….(“A one legged cow is a cow; a two legged…ect.).” This is why Socrates asked Meno for the whole of virtue, and not the parts. Is the following passage using the term “good” tautologically? 

...we define both 'watch' and 'farmer' in terms of the purpose or function which a watch or a farmer are characteristically expected to serve. It follows that the concept of a watch cannot be defined independently of the concept of a good watch nor the concept of a farmer independently of that of a good farmer; and that the criterion of something's being a watch and the criterion of something's being a good watch-and so also for 'farmer' and for all other functional concepts-are not independent of each other (AV., p. 58 )." 

The value of logic is not just that proofs can be derived and demonstrated, but merely attempting to translate an argument from ordinary language into symbolic form discloses problems of meaning that result in many arguments failing this first step of analysis. So far our examination of virtue has identified at least three problems:

  1. We must distinguish between attributes and the more abstract attributes of attributes otherwise a contradiction will result.
  2. There are multiple sets of core virtues and relationships between virtue and attributes such as goodness (VG), justice(VJ), faith (VA), and friendship(VR); nor is it clear if the relations are ones of causal entailment, tautological stipulation, contingent accident, or logically necessary.
  3. We still do not know what virtue (V) is in itself.

Reductio-ad-absurdum direct proof of invalidity that Socrates is “postmodern.”


“Deprived of that context and of that justification, as a result of disruptive and transform native social and moral changes in the late middle ages and the early modern world, moral rules and precepts had to be understood in a new way and assigned some new status, authority, and justification (AV., p. IX)(bold my emphasis)."—Alasdair MacIntyre


A key thesis of After-Virtue claims that postmodernism is a “new” phenomenon,“…a new dark ages which are already upon us (AV., p. 263)”; a “new morality (Ibid., p. 22, 205)”; relatively new the notion was in the culture of the Enlightenment (Ibid.,  p. 26, 38 )";… “Enlightenment project of discovering new rational secular foundations for morality…(Ibid., p. 117)”; "...that rejection the concepts both of value and of fact acquired a new character (Ibid., p. 77). Presenting modern philosophical dilemmas in ethics and epistemology as a “new” modern malaise obscures the fact that postmodernism is really the unresolved philosophical questions of the ancient world. MacIntyre argues that modernism has attacked the premodern Aristotelian philosophy in a conspiracy to promote the aporetic belief that controversies in politics and morals are relativistic and unsettleable (Ibid., p. 6, 8, 26, 118, 227, 252). Interestingly, MacIntyre does say “something like” Aristotelian philosophy could overcome modern ethical relativism (Ibid., p. 118 ). We might be surprised what that “something” could be. Seemingly forgetful of his earlier criticism of analytic empiricism’s new focus on ethical language, MacIntyre acknowledges Plato addressing the incoherence of “evaluative language” of ancient Athens (Ibid., p. 131), but does not mention the Meno dialogue in After-Virtue, and only in passing in “Whose Justice? Which Rationality?” And yet he wrote this same kind of logical analysis as a moral disorder”…we simultaneously and inconsistently treat moral argument as an exercise of our rational powers and as mere expressive assertion-are symptoms of moral disorder…( Ibid., p. 11).” The first half of After Virtue presents the loss of telos as something new (Ibid., p. 62, 148 ), but then later argues the lose of telos in Stoicism anticipated modernity (Ibid., p. 169). Socrates’ method is described in passing as “…those who unreflectively rely on ordinary usage, on what they have been taught, will all too easily find themselves trapped in inconsistency in just the way that Socrates' partners in dialogue so often are (Ibid., p. 134),” but does not further address the aporetic character of the Socratic dialogues, and in fact shuns all aporia.
 

The meaning of postmodernism is sort of a null bit-bucket that one can toss the philosophies of ethical relativism (Ibid., p. xii), ethical skepticism, epistemological relativism, Bloomsbury aesthetes, and nihilism (Ibid., p. 15, 72). Socrates’ skepticism is enough to label him “postmodern” by the philosophical criteria of After Virtue that renders “postmodernism” an ambiguous useless term when considering Socrates was a premodern philosopher. 

The direct proof of invalidity by Reductio ad absurdum works by deriving a contradiction from the examined argument’s own premises thereby showing the conclusion to be impossible—and is therefore invalid (inconsistent). Direct proof is the method that will be applied to the argument that Socrates is a postmodern philosopher according to the criteria found in After Virtue. 

*The indirect proof of validity works by assuming the negation of the conclusion of a proposed valid argument to derive a contradiction to show the negation of the argument’s valid conclusion is absurd—and is therefore valid (consistent). This method will not be used in the argument below.


Definitions:

E= Ethical Skepticism
M= Modern philosophy
~M= Postmodern philosophy
S= Socrates
P=Premodern Philosopher
⊃ : If, then conditional statement
* : and
~ : negation

1.) Ethical skepticism (E) is a postmodernist (~M) philosophy.

2.) Socrates (S) is an Ethical skeptic (E)_

3.) Therefore, Socrates is a postmodernist (~M) philosopher. (1,2, Hypothetical Syllogism) 

The Platonic Socrates is a premodern (P) philosopher (470-399 B.C). The Platonic Socrates represents in the Meno ethical skepticism regarding the questions of virtue. Ethical skepticism, relativism, and nihilism have been represented all through history and are not unique to premodern, modern, or the so-called postmodern eras. The Platonic Socrates discussed the very same “pre-modern concept of the virtues (Ibid., p. 205)” that MacIntyre is preoccupied. 

4.) Socrates is not a postmodern philosopher (~M).

5.) Socrates is a premodern philosopher (P).

6.) Pre-modern philosophy is not postmodernism (~M). 

Summary of premises in sentential logical form:

1.) E ⊃ ~M             

2.) S ⊃ E               

3.) (S ⊃ ~M)           

4.) ~(S ⊃ ~M)    

5.) S ⊃ P               

6.) ~(P ⊃ ~M)

7.) Socrates is a postmodern philosopher (~M) and not the case Socrates is a postmodern philosopher (~M)(3,4, Conjunction) 

REDUCTION AD ABSURDUM: If we accept premises 1 thru 4, then we derived the contradiction in proposition 7 as proof of invalidity. 

7.) (S ⊃ ~M) * ~(S ⊃ ~M)  (3,4, Conjunction)


Ockham’s Razor Shaves All Those Philosophers Who Cannot Shave Themselves.
{(∃x)[Ox * (y)(Py ⊃ Sxy)] * ~Syy}

However, Socrates is not the only philosopher doing his part to undermine Western Civilization; later in history others appeared as biting gadflies against the opinions of the crowd; take for example, the French scholastic theologian, logician, Peter Abelard (1079 –142 A.D.); Scottish Catholic Franciscan priest, friar, professor theology Duns Scotus (1265/66 –1308 ), and English Franciscan friar, theologian William of Ockham (1285-1347 A.D.). 

Peter Abelard was a skillful logician born during the era of Middle Platonism (90 B.C- 300 AD.), and is known as the “Descartes of the 12th century” for his attack on Platonic realism that is the belief universal concepts (words) are actual real things which all existing entities participate. Abelard fiercely opposed this synthesis of Christianity and Platonism by applying his ontological doctrine known as “nominalism,” or “conceptualism” that argues a universal is merely a name (nomen), and not a thing, or object existing objectively in another transcendent world, and to believe so is to erroneously reify abstract concepts; an inherent tendency of language.  Abelard’s critique of reification had little impact at the time, but he still was able to found the first secular university system. He also formulated the legal concept of intent as an element of a criminal act. 

Then again in the 14th century the Franciscan scholar Dun Scotus presented the ontological concept of “univocity of being” which holds being (or beingness) is the property of all real things so that to say “X is a real thing” has one stable meaning so that  “words describing the properties of God mean the same thing as when they apply to people or things.” Unfortunately, this doctrine conflicted with the theological belief that God created all things so now God becomes a being among created beings. According to professor of philosophy and theology, Paul Tyson, author of, “Retuning to Reality,” Cascade Books, (2014), p. 67, Scotus was attempting to create an absolute divide between an infinite God, and finite being to retain God’s absolute transcendence. Tyson traces this evolution of nominalism in the Middle Ages to its dominance in the Enlightenment. 

And yet again the nominalist philosopher Williams of Ockham revisited the problem of universals in the High Middle Ages. Ockham’s metaphysical nominalism involved him in a life and death struggle with Pope John XXII that resulted in him calling the Pope a heretic. Nominalism argues that only individual things exist in reality resulting in an ontological dichotomy of the natural sinful world, and a super-natural transcendent other world. This bi-level ontology creates a separation between the secular world and the sacred (Ibid., p. 54, 74, 141). Tyson notes that this disjointed reality breaks the participatory link between God and all particular created entities--and this happened even before Descartes, Bacon, and Galileo (Ibid., p. 141). Hegel identified this bifocal worldview as displaying a pattern of consciousness formed by two disconnected perceived realities as the “unhappy consciousness (Phenomenology of Spirit, para.197)(pdf.).” 

The critics of postmodernism are trying to distort history giving the false impression that the conflicts between nominalism, relativism, modernism, and Christian theology are somehow wholly unique and new today.

…next:

After-Virtue’s Critique of Metaethical Emotivism