The Ayn Randian Propagandistic Trope Concerning Postmodernism
“…the whole system of
reason finally leads to some point at which reason does not deny itself, does
not abdicate, but transcends itself within itself. “- Paul Tillich
By chance I discovered a video, Critique of Stephen Hicks’
“Explaining Postmodernism,” which is a critique of the book “Explaining
Postmodernism: Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault,”(2010)
authored by the writer Stephen R. C. Hicks who refers to himself as a Randian
Objectivist. The video is well versed in Kantian epistemology and critiques
Hicks’ attack on a philosophical school known as postmodernism. I want to go into greater detail than the video to give additional counter-arguments against
Hicks’ understanding of postmodernism.
I never liked generalized philosophical labels such as
Idealism, Libertarianism, Socialism, or Rationalism since there is nearly always
some mixture of these views influencing a philosopher’s thinking with close
analysis. These terms are useful as tools for topical organization, but are
limited at a certain level of granularity especially while examining specific
logical arguments of an intellectual tradition. The term and concept of
postmodern seems particularly ambiguous and I have wanted to investigate this
issue for sometime now because it is often used as an ad hominem
truncheon in discussions today.
The Fallacy of Circular Reasoning:
The most important step of philosophical analysis is to
methodologically define the term postmodern, which turns out to be a big
problem for this book. Since Hicks is authoring a book on postmodernism the
burden of proof is on him to define how this term is used. Hicks refers to
postmodernism as “anti-realist,” “denies reason,” “subjective,” and “radical.”
Early in his book Hicks wrote, “The term “post-modern” situates the movement
historically and philosophically against modernism”(Loc: 546). In other words
postmodernism is bad since the opposite, modernism, is good.
Hicks describes his methodology as, “…understanding what the
movement sees itself as rejecting and moving beyond will be helpful in
formulating a definition of postmodernism. The modern world has existed for
several centuries, and after several centuries we have good sense of what
modernism is”(Loc: 546). Defining any group by what they think of themselves
might not be the best methodological approach anymore that judging the moral
character of a person by what they say about themselves. Do we really have a
good sense of what modernism is?
However, there is a second even more serious methodological
problem by using how “the movement sees itself,” as a definition since we are
faced with the problem of deciding which movement we will select as postmodern.
Hicks already presupposes what postmodernism is otherwise how else could Hicks
identify any group as a member of the movement! How can one recognize
postmodernism independently of Hicks’ judgment? It seems that the term postmodernism has no essence. Wittgenstein
used the word “game” as an example of a concept that had no essential
meaning. The word’s meaning is how it is used. Likewise, the meaning of
postmodern is whatever Hicks points to since it has no essence. Omnium-gatherum
as a methodology for collecting the particulars of a universal concept will not
work if one does not already have a universal concept of postmodernism. So the
reader must rely on Hicks to point at any particular group he declares
as postmodern. This behavior suggests that Hicks has an unstated criterion for
identifying postmodernism that precludes his identifying some group as
postmodern. And, Hick consciously and unconsciously carries out this
circularity through out the entire book.
The Fallacy of False Dilemma:
This problem of an essential definition gets worse for
Hicks. His concept of postmodernism is extremely vague so that its scope of
meaning can be expanded, or contracted by mere pointing depending on the
effectiveness of any criticism. To better understand Hick’s use of the term
postmodern-ism we can divide speculative philosophy into two general types of
theories of knowledge: The realistic theory of knowledge and the idealistic
theory of knowledge. In the realistic theory knowledge meaning is receiving.
In the idealistic theory meaning is bestowing. Hicks names everything
“objective” as realistic, and everything subjective is “postmodern.” The
problem with this crypto-definition of postmodernism is that objective and
subjective elements cross over into both philosophies of knowledge. Hicks uses
an array of synonyms to describe the realistic epistemologies as the following:
Realistic: Modern, Enlightenment, rational,
competent, universal, absolutist, individualistic, conservative, and objectively true.
On the other hand Hicks describe postmodernism with synonyms
such as:
Idealistic: Non-realist, postmodern,
anti-Enlightenment, anti-reason, incompetent, contingent, relativistic,
collectivist, extremist, and subjective.
With this matrix of dialectical polarities Hicks can setup
pre-constructed fallacies presented as false dilemmas, “Either P, or Q, and ~P,
therefore Q.”
Or symbolically written: [(P v Q) * ~P ] ⊃ Q.
“Either P, or Q” can be expressed as disjunctive
propositions: “either accept Kantian relativism, or embrace objectivism;
either accept postmodernism or embrace the Enlightenment; either embrace
Objective truth or accept postmodern relativism.”
Interestingly, these false dilemmas can be rhetorically
disguised giving the impression that an additional sound argument is being
offered:
“Either not P, or not Q, and P; therefore not Q.”
Or symbolically written: [(~P v ~Q) * P] ⊃ ~Q
This expression can be disguised as “Either reject all truth
with skeptical subjective Kantian relativism, or reject realism based on
universal objective reason. Obviously, those who accept Kantian relativism are
in fact rejecting Objective truth which realism is based.”
The argument’s fallacy is not that its disjunctive argument
form is invalid—that is why it is called an Informal Fallacy, but
that other disjuncts [(P v Q) v (R v S) v (Φ v ψ)] are excluded by definition,
or oversight, or to logically force a false conclusion based on false
disjunctive choices.
Objectivists mindlessly repeat this trope ad infinitum.
And yet another disguise for [(~P v ~Q) * P] ⊃ ~Q,
is the expression: [ P * (~Q v ~P) ] ⊃ ~Q
Which reads as,"For all those that accepted skepticism, they failed to understand the problem of knowledge as essentially rejecting objective science as the key to knowing reality, or avoiding relativism that denies the possibility of all knowledge. Consequently, they fell into relativism."
Now this sophistry is repeated over, and over again throughout the book. Just change Kant's name to Hegel, Kuhn, Heidegger, or whoever is associated with these philosophers for any reason. The author simply pours different content into the same form to reach the same distorted false conclusion.
And yet another disguise for [(~P v ~Q) * P] ⊃ ~Q,
is the expression: [ P * (~Q v ~P) ] ⊃ ~Q
Which reads as,"For all those that accepted skepticism, they failed to understand the problem of knowledge as essentially rejecting objective science as the key to knowing reality, or avoiding relativism that denies the possibility of all knowledge. Consequently, they fell into relativism."
Now this sophistry is repeated over, and over again throughout the book. Just change Kant's name to Hegel, Kuhn, Heidegger, or whoever is associated with these philosophers for any reason. The author simply pours different content into the same form to reach the same distorted false conclusion.
The Insidious Metaphor Logical Fallacy: Φ
Hicks wrote, “Kant was the decisive break with the
Enlightenment and the first major step toward postmodernism” (Loc: 1139). These
synonyms are as ambiguous and misleading as the term postmodern itself. For
example, the term “Enlightenment” has a positive meaning that is unconsciously
imported through a metaphor influencing the reader’s thinking. Not everything
that happened in the Enlightenment was Enlightening; not everything modern is
good; nor was everything in the “Dark Ages” conceptually backwards; and the
“Cold War” had millions of human casualties; and even “Realism” can be an
idealist theory of knowledge subjectively biased. What Hicks referred to as the
“Modern Era,” Kant and Hegel a history of errors. Even if the belief in
objectivism is objective, then that belief provides no evidence whatsoever for
the truth of objectivism. Beware of bare assertions based on insidious
metaphors that unconsciously influence critical thinking.
The Fallacy of Ambiguity: ψ
Hick’s critique of postmodernism is based on the thesis that
Kant’s epistemological skepticism is irrational. “Kant was thus different from
previous skeptics and religious apologists…But earlier skeptics had never been
as sweeping in their conclusions.”(Loc: 1130). If Hicks’ thesis is false, then
the book’s entire philosophical narrative collapses. Hicks wrote, “Thus, the argument runs, Kant
should be placed in the pantheon of Enlightenment greats.[27] That is a
mistake“ (Loc: 897). And again he writes, “His [Kant’s] philosophy is thus a
forerunner of postmodernism’s strong anti-realist and anti-reason”(Loc: 1191).
In another passage he writes, “Any thinker who concludes that in principle
reason cannot know reality is not fundamentally an advocate of reason”
(Loc:1130). This is just one of Hick’s shocking summary judgment of Kantian
epistemology.
Hicks wrote, “Bacon, Descartes, and Locke are modern because
of their philosophical naturalism, their profound confidence in reason, and
especially in the case of Locke, and their individualism,” (Loc: 574). Hicks
avoids any in-depth look at Locke and Descartes because they are
counter-examples to his claims that Kant (1724-1804) is an extreme skeptic.
Kant was a skeptical philosopher of the Enlightenment, but so was the
Enlightenment philosopher Descartes (1576-1650) famous for emphasizing
methodological doubt; and the empiricist David Hume (1711-1776) is the most
famous Enlightenment skeptic of the Western World. Hicks claims
“With Kant then, external reality thus drops almost totally out of the picture,
and we are trapped inescapably in subjectivity—and that is why Kant is a
landmark.” (Loc: 1157). Descartes most famous argument in the “Mediations” is
“I think; therefore, I am,” which is a subjective argument. Would Descartes’
anchoring all knowledge in the subjectivity of “I think,” be as irrational as
Kant? I believe Hicks has his philosophers mixed up, or his concept of postmodern
is simply empty.
In fact, radical skepticism can be traced back all the way
to ancient times such as the Greek philosopher Pyrrho (360 B.C.- 270 B.C.).
“Pyrrhonism is credited with being the first Western school of philosophy to
identify the problem of induction”(Wiki). Pyrrhonism dealt with the same
problems of induction as the radical empiricist skeptic Hume. A strong current
of skepticism can be found throughout the history of Western ideas.
Science today has fundamental questions going back to
Isaac Newton (1642-1726) that are still unsolved today. Newton understood that
the machine paradigm of nature and the absurd observable phenomena of interaction
at a distance such as the non-physical interaction of gravity, or magnetic
repulsion and attraction were scientific mysteries. During Newton’s era these
phenomena were believed to be occult ideas yet modern scientific mechanical
philosophy concluded that there could be no physical interaction without
physical contact. Newton, Hume and Locke agreed that the scientific machine
paradigm could not explain non-physical interaction. Newton wrote, “The notion of
action at a distance is inconceivable. It’s so great an absurdity, I believe no
man who has in philosophical matters that competent faculty of thinking can
ever fall into it…we concede we do not understand the phenomena of the material
world….”(see Chomsky lecture, “The Machine,
the Ghost, and the Limits of Understanding”). Newton’s conclusion is
nothing works by machine principles—there are no machines!
The empiricist, John Locke (1632-1704), wrote further
concerning these scientific mysteries:
“It being, in respect of our Notions, not much more remote from our Comprehension to conceive that God can, if he pleases, superadd to Matter a Faculty of Thinking, than that he should superadd to it another Substance, with a Faculty of Thinking; since we know not wherein Thinking consists, nor to what sort of Substance the Almighty has been pleased to give that Power, which cannot be in any created Being, but merely by the good pleasure and Bounty of the Creator” (Locke, John. 1823: The Works. Ed. by Thomas Tegg, London, IV.III.6).
Consequently,
the “modern” scientists lowered the standard of scientific
intelligibility by adopting the machine paradigm of nature regardless of the
non-material interaction at a distance theoretical problem thereby reducing
science to pragmatic object-manipulation. Pragmatism is the epistemological
foundation for the denial of knowledge (Tillich). The history of modern science
is the very opposite of Hicks’ thesis that modernism is the paradigm of realism. Hicks assumes modern
scientific reasoning had no theoretical problems explaining reality.
“Epistemologically having rejected the notion of an independently existing
reality, postmodernism denies that reason or any other method is a means of
acquiring objective knowledge of that reality” (Loc: 546). By ignoring the
history of modern Western Science, Hicks’ concept of science is a philosophical
caricature of scientism rendering him incapable to understanding the most
fundamental ideas of Kantian epistemology.
No comments:
Post a Comment