Tillich on Chronos and Kairos Time
Experience
“6.3611
We cannot compare any process with the “passage of time”—there is no
such thing—but only with another process (say, with the movement of the
chronometer).”--Wittgenstein
Chronological time, or Chronos,
(the Ancient Greek word, Χρόνος,)
is linear time, or objectively measured clock time of science contrasted with
the other Greek word for time, kairos, (καιρός ) meaning right, proper, exact,
critical time, or lived time. Chronos is quantitative mathematical
time, but Kairos is qualitative time. Personal
psychological lived time, or temporal existentiality, is just as valid as
abstract scientifically measured time. Tillich finds the same distinction in
Heideggerian phenomenology as Existential time and objective time:
“Most radical is Heidegger’s distinction
between “Existential” and objective Time…In his analysis of Kant he indicates
that for himself Time is defined by “selfaffection,”[Sic] grasping oneself or
one’s Personal Existence. Temporality is Existentiality. In distinction from
this qualitative Time, objective Time is the Time of the flight from our own
Personal Existence, into the universal “one,” the “everyone,” the average human
Existence, in which quantitative measurement is necessary and justified. But
this universal Time is not eigentlich, or proper; it is Time
objectified, and it must be interpreted in the light of Existential Time, Time
as immediately experienced, and not vice versa” (Paul Tillich Philosophical
Writings, Vol. 1, ed. Gunther Wenz, 1989, pdf, p. 368).
For Kant, Time is essentially mathematical, linear, and
spatial. A clock is a spatial metaphor (meaning to transfer)
for time. The hands of the clock create a spatial pattern transferred from
lived Time, but clock time is absolutely different than immediately experienced
existential lived time. We can make the clock more accurate, change the spatial
metaphor from non-digital to digital patterns, but existential temporality can
never be reconstructed with observation and analysis of objectively measured
time. Existence cannot be derived from essence. This argument is not based on
the tautology of “my inner experience is my inner experience,” but that
all knowledge assumes an ontological subject/object polarity.
The Ontology of Cognition
Tillich writes, “The unity of participation and
separation in the cognitive situation will always remain a fundamental problem
of philosophy”(PW., p. 338). This epistemological problem emerges from the
“ontology of cognition”(p. 382). When we ask any question about
existence the subject-object structure of reality is already presupposed a
priori. Asking the question of Being, or the meaning of Life is “not
mere subjective emotions with no ontological significance; they are
half-symbolic, half-realistic indication of the structure of Reality
itself”(PW., p. 365). Tillich critically reviews in his writings how
various philosophers struggled with this assumption and the limits of human
cognition. Tillich reminds us Schelling argued that the Principle of Identity
in Thought is “valid only in the realm of essences, not of existence.”
When Thought (Essence) and Being (Existence) are separated –not aligned,
unsynchronized, not attuned--there is no correspondence to Truth. Truth is the
state of thought being in agreement with, or attached to existence. The
separation of subject and object logically implies the dialectical possibility
of their polar unity. So knowledge as a possibility paradoxically depends on
separation and detachment so that “There is no knowledge wither there is no
separation”(PW., p. 383). Kant founded his metaphysics on the ontological
separation between subject and object that characterize finite human reason.
Heidegger believed that the Hegelian critique of Kant’s doctrine of the
thing-in-itself (Ding-an-sich) was a denial of finite human knowledge.
Tillich agrees with the Neo-Kantian critics of mystic ontology that any claim
of a priori knowledge of Being is hubristic irrationalism, but “an
ontology which restricts itself to the structure of finitude is possible.”
Tillich believed--just as Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and Husserl believed--that
the objective impersonal worldview of naturalistic science is swallowing the
creative source of life like a “monstrous mechanism” (PW., p. 366).
Tillich’s philosophical historical survey continues focusing
on the fundamental ontological division between essence (Idea) and existence
(Nature). This ontological division of cognition is the foundation of
existentialist philosophy and the key to a critique of all Hegelian holistic
idealist systems that make truth impersonal. Existentialism is the philosophy
of personal participatory experience from which all interest and decisions
originate—there must be “interest” for actual negation and synthesis (Marx).
Hegelianism lost the participatory subject in an impersonal objective
dialectical process of a progressive teleological history (Kierkegaard). When
Hegelianism claims that “A” is negated into a synthesis with “not-A,” “A” is
simply being labeled as negated. This is because thinking (essence) is
being taken as the same as existence, which is a common error of pure Idealism.
Labeling here is just ideology so there is really no negation of “A.” Marx’s
insight is the Idea will fail if personal participatory interest, passion, and
decision-making is not involved.
Tillich applies this same criticism of confusing thought with existence
to “every rational theory of progressive evolution, idealistic as well as
naturalistic, including the later so-called “scientific Marxism.”(PW.,
p. 359). Marx famously said that philosophers have only interpreted
existence as essences, but the point is to change existence. From these
Schellingian, Hegelian, Marxist, Heideggerian critiques Tillich develops a
systematic ethical and political theology of culture grounded in personal
participatory temporal existential subjectivity, or Kairos
experience. (Paul Tillich, Theology of Culture, 1970, pdf.).
The Kairos Circle
“Awareness of a Kairos is a matter of vision…. It is not a
matter of detached observation but of involved experience.”—Tillich,
“Systematic Theology, Vol. III, p. 370.
Tillich develops Kairos into an
existential theology of participation that is more of an “attitude of
consciousness,” than a political party, or a popular cultural fashion. The
word Kairos is used in the New Testament as meaning, “fulfillment of time,”
or “God’s timing” referring to the churches experiencing the “self-transcending
dynamics of history.” Kairos is the opportune time, the right time, or the
harvest time of crops. Kairos is the occasion of an existential decision made
in a concrete historical situation based on an analysis, and anticipation of
something old passing and the new emerging, but calculation does not produce
the Kairos-experience. Scientific-technical foresight of unknown forces working
along with human decisions makes predicting the world historical process
impossible.
In the Greek sense of the word,
Kairos means “any practical purpose which a good occasion of some action is
given”(Ibid., p. 369). Kairos is used in the New Testament
when Jesus speaks of the “signs of the times,” or when Jesus said the time for
his death had not come yet; John the Baptist and Jesus used it to announce the
fulfillment of time for the Kingdom of God; or when the prophetic Spirit arises
in the Pauline era. Paul uses it in speaking of Christ, the “great
Kairos,” that can enter history at any time and is selected as the “center of
history” which can be re-experienced again, and again (meaningful
repetition of time, not mathematical linear time). But not every Kairos is of
the same historical importance. Relative “kairoi” (plural meaning “the times”)
describes when the Church reforms itself against a distorted age, or refuses to
reform against heresy.
The Kairos experience can describe
a world-historical paradigm shift in an era of tyranny and domination that
suffers from paradigm entropy by failing to provide a meaningful worldview
resulting in collapse that makes way for a new paradigm, a new society—and a
New Being-- to emerge in history. There is difficulty distinguishing a Kairos
from a relative kairoi. Kairoi can be
demonically distorted and tragically wrong.
The term Kairos was used after WWI
in central Europe to describe religious socialism, but it was also used “…by
the nationalist movement, which, through the voice of nazism, attacked the
great Kairos and everything for which it stands. The latter use was a
demonically distorted experience of a Kairos and led to self-destruction. The
Spirit nazism claimed was the spirit of the false prophets, prophets who spoke
for an idolatrous nationalism and racialism. Against them the Cross of the
Christ was and is the absolute criterion” (Ibid., p. 371).
Kairos is a normative concept, not
just a description. The Kairos is the moment the archer decides to release his
arrow aimed at a target. Tillich tells
us that no date foretold by Kairos has ever been correct. No situation foretold
by Kairos ever came into being, but history has been changed. History does
not progress in a steady predicable rhythm, but undergoes violence change,
extreme creativity, extremely dormant periods, oppression, possibilities,
cruelty, liberation, and expectation.
In 1919
Paul Tillich formed the “Kairos Circle” with Eduard Heimann, Carl
Mennicke, Arnold Wolfers and others to ask the church to be open to socialism
and social democracy, and a synthesis of Christianity with socialism. Tillich
published the “Journal for Religious Socialism” between 1920-1927 for
the group and later from 1930 published the “New Journal for Socialism.”
Tillich declared that theology and ethics must “step forward in opposition
to the capitalist and militarist order of society in which we find ourselves,
and whose final consequences became obvious in the World War.” Tillich’s
ultimate goal is for persons to “experience the divine in everything human,
the eternal in everything temporal”(“Paul Tillich as a Systemic
Theologian,” by Oswald Bayer in “The Cambridge Companion to Paul
Tillich, Ed. by Russell Re Manning, Cambridge University Press,
2009, Pdf., p.19).
Peter Gabriel in Athens, Greece
"Lay Your Hands On Me"
Sat in the corner of the Garden
Grill, with plastic flowers
on the window sill
No more miracles, loaves and
fishes, been so busy with the
washing of the dishes
Reaction level's much too high -
I can do without the stimuli
I'm living way beyond my ways
and means, living in the
zone of the in betweens
I can see the flashes on the
frozen ocean, static charge of
the cold emotion
Watched on by the distant eyes -
watched on by the silent
hidden spies
But still the warmth flows
through me
And I sense you know me well
No luck, no golden chances
No mitigating circumstances now
It's only common sense
There are no accidents around
here
I am willing - lay your hands on
me
I am ready - lay your hands on
me
I believe - lay your hands on
me, over me
Working in gardens, thornless
roses, fat men play with their
garden hoses
Poolside laughter has a cynical
bite, sausage speared by the
cocktail satellite
I walk away from from light and
sound, down stairways
leading underground
But still the warmth flows
through me
And I sense you know me well
It's only common sense
There are no accidents around
here
I am willing - lay your hands on
me
I am ready - lay your hands on
me
I believe - lay your hands on
me, over me
over me
No comments:
Post a Comment